Date: 20021206  
Docket: 98/42  
Citation: 2002 NLCA 72  
IN THE SUPREME COURT OF NEWFOUNDLAND AND LABRADOR  
COURT OF APPEAL  
BETWEEN:  
NEWFOUNDLAND ASSOCIATION  
OF PUBLIC EMPLOYEES  
APPELLANT/  
RESPONDENT ON  
CROSS-APPEAL  
AND:  
HER MAJESTY THE QUEEN IN  
RIGHT OF NEWFOUNDLAND, as  
represented by Treasury Board, and  
the Minister of Justice  
RESPONDENT/  
APPELLANT ON  
CROSS-APPEAL  
Coram: Marshall, Steele and Roberts JJ.A.  
Court Appealed From: Supreme Court of Newfoundland and Labrador  
Trial Division, 1997 St. J. 1687 & 1997 St. J. 1717  
Appeal Heard:  
Judgment Rendered:  
January 10-11, 2001  
December 6, 2002  
Reasons for Judgment by Marshall J.A. [paras. 1-640]  
Concurrence by Steele J.A. [para. 641]  
Concurrence by Roberts J.A. [para. 642]  
Counsel for the Appellant: Sheila Greene  
Counsel for the Respondent: Donald Burrage, Q.C.  
Page: 2  
Marshall, JA:  
[1] This appeal addresses entitlement of female employees in the health care  
sector, who are represented by the Newfoundland Association of Public  
Employees, popularly known as NAPE, to retroactive pay equity  
adjustments for three fiscal years extending from April 1, 1988, to March  
31, 1991. Government purports to justify its refusal to make those  
payments, which the union had succeeded in negotiating, on the basis of its  
subsequent fiscal restraint legislation. In so doing, Government is relying  
specifically on a section in the legislation that prohibited implementation of  
pay equity agreements retroactively, and provided that any existing  
agreement calling for retroactive payments should be void.  
[2] The issue of the employees’ entitlement comes before this Court in an  
appeal from a decision of a judge in the Trial Division allowing the  
Government’s application for judicial review of a majority arbitration  
decision which had allowed the union’s grievance alleging improper refusal  
to pay the retroactive wage adjustments negotiated by NAPE. In allowing  
the application, and setting aside the decision, the judge ruled the  
Arbitration Board had erred in assuming jurisdiction in the circumstances  
obtaining. The judge then went on to hold, alternatively, on the supposition  
the Board was seized with jurisdiction, that the majority further erred in  
finding the legislative provision relied upon by Government to justify its  
refusal to make the retroactive wage equity payments violated the Charter.  
[3] Before proceeding to outline the backdrop to this appeal, mention should be  
made that this proceeding is concerned only with entitlement to those  
payments which, but for the legislative intervention, would unquestionably  
have fallen due as scheduled. After that intervention had run its course,  
arrangements were concluded to both parties’ satisfaction for payment of  
the adjustments, excepting those that were originally contemplated to have  
fallen due in the three fiscal years spanning April 1, 1988, to March 31,  
1991.  
[4] It should likewise be noted that it took more than nine years for the issue of  
the retroactive entitlement to wend its way to a hearing before this Court.  
This observation is not made in any way as a criticism. A number of  
reasons exist for that time span, not the least of which is the overall  
complexity of the matter. In that regard, this judgment would be remiss  
were it to fail to acknowledge at its outset indebtedness to both counsel for  
Page: 3  
the quality of their submissions which significantly assisted distillation of  
the complexities, and analysis of the issues, presented by this appeal.  
Background circumstances:  
÷
the promise:  
[5] Counsel for NAPE opened her oral submissions by styling these  
proceedings as having arisen from a broken promise to remedy a long-  
standing injustice. She identifies this injustice as the underpayment of  
female employees in the health care system in comparison with their male  
counterparts.  
[6] The promise that counsel contends was broken is contained in a Pay Equity  
Agreement entered into between NAPE and Government on June 24, 1988.  
It was agreed that that Agreement would be added as a schedule to six  
subsisting collective agreements governing employment of units in the  
health care sector represented by NAPE. The stated purpose of the pay  
equity addendum was to “achieve pay equity by redressing systemic gender  
discrimination in compensation for work performed by employees in female  
dominated classes ...”. It set out a procedure and timetable for  
accomplishing that objective.  
[7] The procedure detailed a method for evaluating the gender discrimination  
between female and male dominated classes of employees. This was  
designed to measure the monetary adjustments necessary to bring the hourly  
wage rates of affected female classes in correspondence with comparable  
male wage policy lines. The timetable provided for pay equity to be  
achieved within five years. The first pay equity wage adjustment was to be  
made on April 1, 1988. This was to be followed by payments on the first  
days of April in each year thereafter, to and including April 1, 1992. The  
first four of these annual payments were capped at 1% of the payroll for the  
health care sector in the fiscal year ending March 31, 1988, with any  
remainder being payable in its entirety on April 1, 1992, being the fifth  
anniversary of the first effective payment date.  
[8] The quantum of the wage adjustments between the classes admitted to no  
immediate simple calculation. Thus, the Pay Equity Agreement could not  
be implemented by simply resorting to readily ascertainable sums, and  
dividing them by the five years contemplated for realizing the pay equity  
policy. The services of financial consultants were necessary to evaluate the  
Page: 4  
subsisting gender discrimination between the comparable classes of  
employees before calculation of the requisite wage adjustments could be  
finalized. The consultant’s report was not finalized until March 20, 1991,  
and not received by the steering committee charged with implementation of  
the June 24, 1988, Pay Equity Agreement until July, 1991. It was, therefore,  
only after the first four scheduled wage adjustment dates had passed that  
Government was in a position to respond to its undertaking to make the  
wage adjustment payments.  
÷
alleged breach of promise:  
[9] In the meantime, while the quantum of the wage adjustments under the  
addendum to the six collective agreements was being determined, the  
Province was passing through a serious economic downturn which  
constrained Government to adopt a policy of severe fiscal restraint. The  
downturn was the product of a deteriorating economic climate that prevailed  
in the early 1990’s. The policy resulted in wage restraint legislation  
freezing wage scales and restricting payments under pay equity agreements.  
The legislation is purported to affect entitlement to the wage adjustments  
claimed by NAPE in the proceedings at bar.  
[10] Initially, these restraints were enacted in the Public Sector Restraint Act,  
1991, S.N. c. 3, which passed into law on April 18, 1991, with effect from  
March 31, 1991. It legislated a one year period of restraint on monetary  
benefits payable to all public sector employees for a one year period  
beginning on April 1, 1991, and ending on March 31, 1992. That statute  
was supplanted by the Public Sector Restraint Act, 1992, S.N. 1992, c. P-  
41.1 which replaced and extended the restraint period for an additional two  
years. It overlapped the period imposed in the 1991 enactment and affected  
future increases that had been granted through collective bargaining. As the  
1992 Act applied to employees who were subject to collective agreements,  
commencements of restraint periods varied according to the bargaining  
status of the particular collective agreement in relation to April 1, 1991. For  
most collective agreements the expiry of the restraint period would occur  
sometime in 1994, roughly two years after the second legislative measure.  
For the parties in this appeal, the expiry date worked out to March 31, 1993.  
[11] The 1991 statute contained a provision that remained unimpaired by, and  
was continued in force under, the 1992 Act. Government relies upon that  
legislative provision as extinguishing its obligation to make the retroactive  
Page: 5  
pay equity adjustments under its agreement concluded on June 24, 1988,  
with NAPE that had accrued due under the Pay Equity Agreement up to  
March 31, 1991. The provision whose effectiveness, which lies at the  
center of this appeal, was initially enacted through s. 9 of the 1991 statute  
and reads:  
C
9.(1) Notwithstanding the terms and conditions of a pay equity  
agreement contained in a collective agreement or added by agreement  
to an existing collective agreement, no pay equity agreement shall  
contain a provision which implements that pay equity agreement  
retroactively.  
C
C
(2) Where there is a provision in a pay equity agreement which  
provides that the pay equity agreement shall be implemented  
retroactively, that provision is void.  
(3) Notwithstanding the other provisions of this Act, a pay equity  
agreement may be negotiated or implemented, but the 1st pay equity  
wage adjustment date shall be the date on which the pay equity wage  
adjustment is agreed upon.  
C
C
(4) This section applies whether the pay equity agreement is  
reached or the pay equity wage adjustment is agreed upon before or  
after the date this Act comes into force.  
(5) In this section “pay equity agreement” means an agreement  
between a public sector employer and a group of public sector  
employees to recognize the compensation practice which is based  
primarily on the relative value of work performed, irrespective of the  
gender of employees, and includes a requirement that no employer  
shall establish or maintain a difference between compensation paid to  
male and female employees, employed by that employer, who are  
performing work of equal or comparable value.  
[12] While Government relies on this legislation as absolving it from its  
obligation to make the retroactive pay equity adjustments under the 1988  
agreement, NAPE views it as a broken promise to rectify a long-standing  
injustice stemming from the practice of underpaying women in the public  
service. It argues that this injustice casts an unfair burden upon female  
dominated classes of employees in the health care sector of shouldering an  
inequitable share of the exigencies of public fiscal problems. Accordingly,  
it filed grievances seeking redress for the alleged breach of promise.  
Page: 6  
÷
the union’s grievance:  
[13] By April 22, 1991, just four days after the initial legislation came into  
effect, NAPE filed nine grievances on behalf of employees in the six  
bargaining units. These grievances alleged violations of the respective  
collective agreements as a result of the Government’s failure to pay the  
retroactive equity adjustments incorporated into each agreement through the  
June 24, 1988, Pay Equity Agreement. The grievances claimed:  
C
Full redress on behalf of all employees affected by the Employer’s  
actions including payment of wage adjustments in accordance with  
the Pay Equity provisions of all Collective Agreements plus interest  
of two percent (2%) per month.  
[14] The grievances alleged that the Government’s failure to pay the adjustments  
were “contrary to the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms”. It was  
the equality rights guaranteed under s. 15 of the Charter which NAPE was  
alleging the Government infringed. It maintained this stance throughout the  
proceedings subsequent to the filing of those grievances. Indeed, this  
alleged constitutional violation constitutes the main plank in the appeal at  
bar. Contending that s. 9 of the restraint legislation violated s. 15 of the  
Charter and was not saved by s. 1, the union has consistently contended s.  
9 was of no effect, and that the unfulfilled undertaking to have made the  
three wage adjustments up to and including April 1, 1991, stands as a  
broken promise which it is entitled to have redressed.  
÷
the arbitration:  
[15] In a letter dated April 26, 1991, directed to the President of Treasury Board,  
the Minister responsible for collective bargaining and the administration of  
the collective agreements, NAPE advised of its nominee to the Arbitration  
Board. On May 13, 1991, the Director of the Treasury Board’s Collective  
Bargaining Division responded by letter stating the employer’s position,  
which has been steadfastly maintained throughout these proceedings, that  
“no grievance exists in this matter and as such the matter is not arbitral”.  
Undeterred, the Union wrote to the Minister of Employment and Labour  
Relations on July 10, 1991, asking him to appoint an employer nominee to  
the Arbitration Boards in accordance with provisions of the collective  
agreements. This resulted in NAPE being advised on July 29, 1991, by the  
Assistant Deputy Minister of the Minister’s Department of the name of the  
employer’s nominee to deal with the alleged violations.  
Page: 7  
[16] The difficulty in the constitution of the Arbitration Board did not end with  
the appointment of the employer’s nominee, however. The respective  
nominees were unable to agree upon a chairperson for the Board.  
Consequently, on March 11, 1992, the solicitor for NAPE requested the  
Minister of Employment and Labour Relations to appoint a person to chair  
the Board. This resulted in an appointment by the Minister on April 21,  
1992.  
[17] Hearings commenced on October 16, 1995. It had been agreed that the  
grievance involving the Newfoundland Hospital and Nursing Home  
Association would be treated as representative of all pay equity grievances  
in dispute. At the outset of those hearings, the chairperson brought up a  
new issue for the Board’s consideration when he advised that his spouse  
was a member of the Newfoundland and Labour Nurses Union and was  
employed in the public health care sector. This elicited a submission from  
Government that the chairperson should disqualify himself due to a  
reasonable apprehension of bias. The latter declined and the Board  
proceeded as constituted, filing its decision on April 14, 1997.  
Arbitration Board’s decision:  
÷
overview:  
[18] While three separate decisions were filed by the Board, there was unanimity  
on two preliminary matters. Thus all three, including the Government  
nominee, agreed there was no reasonable apprehension of bias justifying the  
chairperson’s disqualification. All were in accord as well that the Board  
had jurisdiction to hear the grievances, so that the same were arbitrable.  
[19] The grievances presented two substantive issues beyond the two preliminary  
ones. They did not receive the same degree of unanimity amongst the  
Board’s members. The first focused on the language of s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation, and converged on the extent of its prohibition of retroactive  
implementation of pay equity agreements, such as those with which this  
appeal is concerned. The second issue questions s. 9’s conformity with the  
equality rights entrenched in s. 15 of the Charter; and, if in violation of s.  
15, asks whether such a violation is justifiable under s. 1 of the Charter.  
Thus, one issue goes to statutory interpretation of s. 9 of the legislation,  
whilst the other concentrates on that provision’s constitutionality.  
Page: 8  
÷
chairperson’s decision:  
[20] The chairperson turned first to the statutory interpretation issue to explore  
the effect of the language in s. 9 upon the Pay Equity Agreement. In  
addressing that issue, whilst holding up s-s. 9(1)’s prohibition against pay  
equity agreements containing “a provision which implements that pay  
equity agreement retroactively”, and s-s. 9(2)’s declaration that any such  
provision is void, the chairperson defined “a retroactive provision” as “one  
which operates prior to the date on which the contract or other legal  
enactment is entered into or enacted”. Then, after observing that the Pay  
Equity Agreement in dispute was entered into on June 24, 1988, he reasoned  
the effect of s-s. 9(1) and s-s. 9(2) “is to eliminate the retroactive period  
prior to June 24, 1988”.  
[21] The decision then turns to consider the effect of s. 9 upon “pay equity and  
adjustments scheduled to be paid subsequent to the date a Pay Equity  
Agreement had been entered into”. Here, the chairperson focused on s-s.  
9(3), noting that it permits “negotiation or implementation of pay equity  
agreements”, whilst clearly ensuring “that pay equity adjustments would be  
paid out only as prescribed by the statute”. To accomplish this objective,  
his decision goes on to note at p. 81, s-s. 9(3):  
C
... designed a method that would identify the first pay equity wage  
adjustment date regardless of any contrary date that might be  
expressed in a pay equity agreement. Simply put, the date on which  
the amount of pay equity was agreed would constitute the first pay  
equity wage adjustment date. By this method pay equity adjustments  
were subject to restraint.  
[22] In addressing the restraints subsequent to the date of entry into the Pay  
Equity Agreement affected under s-s. 9(3)’s terms, the chairperson  
commented on the length of the process of determining the quantum of pay  
equity adjustments, whilst observing, as already mentioned in preceding  
para. 8, that “the amounts to be paid were not finally calculated until March  
20, 1991”. The upshot of this, he went on to observe, was that “a significant  
three year payout would have been due on April 1, 1991” under the Pay  
Equity Agreement. However, he construed s-s. 9(3) as obviating that  
obligation.  
[23] In that construction of s-s. 9(3), the chairperson relies on a distinction that  
he perceived between the phrases of “the first pay equity adjustment date”  
and “the pay equity wage adjustment” as utilized in that subsection. He  
Page: 9  
viewed the former phrase as temporal dealing with time, and the latter as  
quantitative dealing with amount. Thus, the latter connoted, in his view,  
“the total amount of the pay equity adjustment that must be agreed upon”,  
whilst the former meant “the first date of payment of a portion of that total  
amount”. From that standpoint, the chairperson’s decision interprets s-s.  
9(3) as restricting the initial date of payment towards the total quantum of  
pay equity adjustments to, in the subsection’s own words, “the date on  
which the pay equity adjustment is agreed upon”. This was construed by  
Government as effectively erasing the obligation to make the aggregate  
payments as contemplated in the Pay Equity Agreement that fell due in the  
three fiscal years spanning April 1, 1988 to March 31, 1991. It was over  
that erasure that the union had grieved.  
[24] The chairperson summed up the effect of his construction of s-s. 9(3) as  
ensuring “the anticipated amount would not be paid as intended”. Hence,  
there “would be no lump sum for previous periods, thereby achieving  
significant savings, or restraint”. It was only “the amount associated with  
the first pay equity adjustment date” that “would be permitted on that date”,  
the chairperson held. He went on to explain that s-s. 9(4) buttressed this  
point of view by making it clear that s. 9 applies whether a “Pay Equity  
Agreement is reached” or a “pay equity wage adjustment is agreed upon”,  
either “before or after the date this Act comes into force”. This, he wrote,  
witnesses an intent “to ensure that no agreement past or future dealing with  
pay equity will escape the effect of the restraint legislation”.  
[25] On the basis of the foregoing reasoning, the chairperson’s decision at p. 83  
expresses satisfaction that:  
C
... the language of s. 9 is clear and unambiguous and had the effect of  
extinguishing the obligations on government ... to provide pay equity  
adjustments for the period April 1, 1988 to March 31, 1991.  
[26] Having so resolved the statutory interpretation issue, the chairperson turned  
to the question whether the legislative extinguishment of Government’s  
obligations under the Pay Equity Agreement met constitutional muster.  
This issue entailed inquiry into whether s. 9 violates the Charter and, if so,  
whether the infringement was justifiable under s. 1 of the Charter.  
[27] In regard to the first question, the chairperson rejected the Government’s  
argument that the effect of s. 9 of the restraint legislation was merely to  
substitute one process for another which did not infringe s. 15 of the  
Charter. He held at p. 87 that in:  
Page: 10  
C
... curtailing the adjustments required under the Pay Equity  
Agreement, s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act disproportionately  
and adversely affected female employees working in the public sector  
by depriving them of the benefit of pay equity in comparison with  
employees in male-dominated job classifications who are paid in  
accordance with the value of their work. The legislation permits and  
extends discriminatory compensation practices as between male and  
female employees in a context in which those practices have been  
actually identified and quantified.  
C
In the result, I am satisfied that s. 9 of the Public Sector  
Restraint Act violates s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
[28] Having found this violation of the Charter, the chairperson’s decision turns  
to explore whether s. 9 of the restraint legislation was yet saved by s. 1 of  
the Charter, as a reasonable limitation of s. 15's equality guarantee which  
could be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society. In so  
doing, the decision relied on the standard laid down in R. v. Oakes, [1986]  
1 S.C.R. 103. The criteria identified in that authority, in which context the  
chairperson conducted his analysis of the s. 1 issue, are the well recognized  
yardsticks of the importance of legislative objective; the impugned  
measure’s rational connection to that objective; minimal impairment of the  
constitutional protection; and, proportionality of the measure’s effect in  
realizing the legislative object.  
[29] Referring to comments recorded in Hansard by the President of Treasury  
Board on the restraint measure’s introduction, the chairperson found s. 9  
met the test of sufficient importance to warrant overriding of the  
constitutionally protected equality right’s violation. The importance, his  
decision records, was the established “pressing and substantial objective of  
saving money” that he had earlier expressed his satisfaction was necessary  
“to reduce an escalating deficit in circumstances where the financial health  
and well-being of the Province was at stake”.  
[30] As to the second test of rational connection, noting that the legislative  
purpose was “to reduce pay equity wage adjustment expenditures” the  
chairperson found s. 9 “well-tailored to suit that purpose”. Thus, he found  
the second of the four criteria to have been met.  
[31] However, the chairperson concluded that Government had not met the third  
criterion. Thus, he wrote that he was “satisfied the government has not  
shown that it had a reasonable basis for concluding that it had complied  
Page: 11  
with the principle of minimal impairment in seeking to attain its objective of  
pay equity cost restraint”. In reaching this conclusion, once more resorting  
to Hansard, the chairperson expressed his satisfaction that “only one  
alternative to the infringement might have been considered by government”.  
This, his reading of Hansard indicated, was the lay off of some 900  
employees as mentioned by the President of Treasury Board as the only  
other option left open to Government.  
[32] On the other hand, the chairperson’s decision notes, the Leader of the  
Opposition proposed some thirteen other alternatives. While stating he was  
not necessarily advocating any or all of those measures “should have been  
chosen by government to minimize the infringement”, the chairperson stated  
he was “merely pointing them out”. Then, he went on to note that the  
testimony of an Assistant Secretary to the Treasury Board who gave  
evidence before the Board attested to “other money-saving mechanisms”.  
Although acknowledging that courts “accord governments a measure of  
deference and flexibility” in this area of Charter analysis, the decision finds  
“there is more than sufficient evidence in this case to establish that several  
other less restrictive means were available to government which would have  
minimized the infringement”. On the basis of this reasoning the chairperson  
concluded the third criterion had not been met.  
[33] With respect to the final test of proportionality of the restraint measure’s  
effect, proceeding on the footing that this required a balancing of the  
measure’s objective against the infringement of the constitutionally  
protected civil liberty, the chairperson accepted that that balancing process  
entailed inquiry into whether the Charter violation was too high a price to  
pay for the benefit of attainment of the restraint legislation’s objective.  
[34] The chairperson answered that inquiry by concluding the “infringement was  
too high a price to pay for the benefit of the law”. Thus, he effectively held  
the violation of the equality rights guaranteed under s. 15 of the Charter, by  
the extension of discriminatory compensation practices as between male and  
female employees, as perpetrated through the restraint measures enacted in  
s. 9 of the legislation, exacted a disproportionate price vis à vis the  
legislation’s objective of furthering the province’s financial health and well-  
being.  
[35] Based, therefore, on s. 9's failure to meet the tests of minimal impairment  
and proportionality of effect, the chairperson found that s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation was not saved by s. 1 of the Charter. Accordingly, the  
Page: 12  
provisions of s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act were held to be void,  
and the original terms and conditions of the Pay Equity Agreement,  
including the obligations to make pay equity adjustments as therein  
prescribed, were declared to prevail.  
[36] In a statement that now is echoed by NAPE in its insistence that these  
proceedings seek to redress a broken promise, the chairperson asserted the  
employer’s failure to fully implement the Pay Equity Agreement in  
accordance with its terms violated not only that Agreement, but also the  
undertaking given in Article 4.01 of the representative collective agreement  
that there should be no gender discrimination with respect to any employee.  
As a result, the chairperson’s decision ends by directing the employer “to  
pay any compensation from the violation” of the Pay Equity Agreement.  
÷
union nominee’s decision:  
[37] NAPE’s nominee concurred in the result of the chairperson’s award, but  
partially dissented in three respects regarding the reasoning leading to the  
result.  
[38] In the first place, the union nominee disagreed with the chair having  
proceeded on the footing that s. 9 of the restraint legislation extinguished  
full entitlement to the three year wage adjustments claimed by the union in  
the proceedings at bar. In this regard, NAPE’s nominee takes the position  
that the only period caught under s. 9 was that between April 1, 1988, when  
wage adjustments were originally scheduled to commence, and June 24,  
1988, when the Pay Equity Agreement was entered into. In maintaining this  
stance, NAPE’s representative on the Board states, “the commonly  
accepted meaning of a retroactive provision is clear: it is one which operates  
prior to the date on which the contract or other legal enactment is entered  
into or enacted”.  
[39] From this standpoint, he reasons that any wage equity adjustment payable  
subsequent to June 24, 1988, when the Agreement at bar was entered into,  
“would not give rise to retroactive implementation”, and thus would be  
unaffected by the prohibition of retroactive implementation of pay equity  
agreements enacted through the first two subsections of s. 9.  
[40] In construing wage equity adjustments payable after June 24, 1988, to be  
unaffected by s-s. 9(3), the Union’s nominee’s first departure from the  
chairperson’s reasoning emerges. As the summary in preceding paras. 23  
and 24 of the latter’s decision recounts, the chairperson construed the  
Page: 13  
language of s-s. 9(3) as ensuring the amount of the wage adjustments would  
not be paid on the dates falling in the three fiscal years spanning April 1,  
1998, to March 31, 1991, as contemplated by the Pay Equity Agreement;  
and, as foreclosing any “lump sum for previous payment” on April 1, 1991.  
It was only “the amount associated with the first pay equity adjustment  
date” as set by s-s. 9(3) that would fall due on April 1, 1991, under this  
interpretation.  
[41] Disagreeing with that construction of s-s. 9(3), NAPE’s nominee maintains  
“the date upon which the pay equity adjustments were agreed upon” was not  
when the specific amount was determined by the fiscal consultants on  
March 20, 1991, but when the Agreement was entered into, i.e. June 24,  
1988. This follows, he reasons, because the legislation speaks not of the  
date “upon which the amount of the pay equity adjustment is determined”,  
but rather of the date “upon which the parties agreed to the pay equity  
adjustment itself”. This interpretation, he goes on to add, is reinforced by s-  
s. 9(4). Had the Legislature “meant to refer to the date the amount was  
agreed to”, he explains, “it would have said so explicitly”. In underscoring  
that it had not been so explicit, the union nominee argues that, in setting the  
“1st pay equity adjustment date” at when “the pay equity adjustment is  
agreed upon”, s-s. 9(3) was fixing unambiguously the first permissible  
payment date “when a commitment to institute pay equity is reached, not the  
date when a specific amount is determined”. Moreover, he goes on still  
further to add, even were any ambiguity construed to lie in s-s. 9(3) in that  
regard, then “well-established rules of construction” would “dictate an  
interpretation consistent with the agreement of the parties to redress  
discrimination through the achievement of pay equity”. In his view, such  
consistency would lead to the same conclusion which he interprets the  
provision to unambiguously convey. NAPE’s nominee concluded that as of  
April 1, 1992 “the full amount of the pay equity adjustments must be paid  
...”, rather than just the “amount associated with the first pay equity  
adjustment date” as the chairperson had determined.  
[42] Alternatively, NAPE’s nominee also reasons in his second departure from  
the chairperson’s interpretation of s. 9, even if the legislation shielded  
Government from making payments due under the Pay Equity Agreement  
up to and including the 1990-91 fiscal year, so that “the first pay equity  
adjustment be no earlier than April 1, 1991", and assuming arguendo that  
“retroactivity were to include amounts payable prior to that date” which  
Page: 14  
assumption the union nominee rejects in his primary position, there was  
nonetheless “no basis for changing the level of the wage adjustment due on  
that date”. Underscoring that the legislation “does not provide that the first  
wage adjustment date shall entail a deferral of the pay equity entitlement”,  
he reasons that “effective April 1, 1991, the government was obliged to pay  
the wage rate due in the fourth year (1991-1992) in respect of pay equity  
adjustments” and that in “the year 1992-93 (the fifth year) the balance of the  
pay equity adjustment was payable in accordance with the Pay Equity  
Agreement”. This would result in the full amount of the pay equity that  
would have been received under the Agreement falling due on April 1,  
1992.  
[43] NAPE’s nominee, in his final divergence from this phase of the  
Chairperson’s reasoning, then looked to an article in the collective  
agreement to buttress this alternate position. Thus, quoting the employer’s  
undertaking in Article 4.01 that there “shall be no discrimination” affecting  
wage rates by reason of gender, he concluded that, “once the amount of the  
discrepancy attributable to gender was determined”, the continuance of “pay  
differential wage rates ... on the basis of sex” contravened that Article.  
NAPE’s nominee identified the date when the amount of the discrepancy  
was determined as March 20, 1991, which was when the financial  
consultants’ report evaluating the subsisting gender discrimination was  
finalized. This resulted, he reasoned, in Government being precluded from  
taking the position that “no discrimination has been established”. However,  
he recognized that the statutory freezes on increases to pay scales also  
enacted under the legislation would preclude the “granting of increases,  
even though they resulted from discrimination”; and, that those freezes for  
the parties involved in the arbitration began on April 1, 1991 and ended on  
March 31, 1993. The reason for the expiry date falling on March 31, 1993,  
has already been explained in preceding para. 10. As a result, NAPE’s  
nominee went on to reason “from April 1, 1993, forward, there was no  
statutory restriction on the parties making wage adjustments to redress  
discriminatory provisions of the agreement”. Accordingly he concluded,  
“as of April 1, 1993, the full amount of the pay equity adjustments must be  
paid to affected employees in order to comply with Article 4.01 of the  
Collective Agreement”.  
[44] Apart from these differences with the chair’s disposition, the union nominee  
also took exception with its reliance on Hansard in interpreting s. 9 and with  
Page: 15  
its alleged finding that the pay equity adjustments for the period from June  
24, 1988, to March 31, 1991 were retroactive. Otherwise, the decision of  
NAPE’s nominee concurred with the chairperson’s analysis of the  
Charter’s application and, consequently, with the latter’s decision that the  
affected employees should be paid compensation due under the Pay Equity  
Agreement.  
÷
employer’s nominee decision:  
[45] The Government nominee agreed with the chairperson’s interpretation of s.  
9, but disagreed with his constitutional analysis, with the result that he  
dissented from the majority view that the affected employees were entitled  
to be compensated for wage adjustments falling due between April 1, 1988,  
and March 31, 1991, under the Pay Equity Agreement. In reaching that  
conclusion, Government’s nominee to the Board agreed that s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation infringed s. 15 of the Charter. He did not agree,  
however, with the opinion shared by the other Board members that the  
violation was saved by s. 1.  
[46] In his analysis of s. 1's application, the Government nominee concurred with  
his colleagues’ conclusions that the restraint legislation was of sufficient  
importance to override a constitutionally guaranteed Charter right, and that  
s. 9 met the rationally connection test. However, he did not agree that s. 9  
failed to fulfill the minimal impairment and proportionality criteria. Having  
determined the measure’s objective sufficiently important to brook a  
Charter infringement, he underscored that it did not place a total ban on  
pay equity agreements, but merely eliminated retroactive payments “in a  
time of fiscal restraint when other employees were being laid off or had  
negotiated wage increases eliminated”. This being the case, the  
Government nominee was of the opinion that “the impugned law did not go  
further than necessary to achieve a legitimate objective of the Legislature”.  
[47] Although conceding there were other means of realizing the objective of  
meeting the fiscal exigencies detailed by the President of Treasury Board,  
the Government nominee suggested whenever the Legislature allocates  
“scarce resources between competing but legitimate groups”, it lies neither  
with “the court or arbitrators to substitute their opinions for the collective  
wisdom of the Legislature”. Hence, in distancing himself from the majority  
view that s. 9 fails to satisfy the minimal impairment test, he placed  
Page: 16  
significant weight on the thesis that a high degree of judicial deference  
should be accorded such legislative budgetary choices.  
[48] As to the proportionality question, Government’s nominee concluded “the  
Legislature struck a reasonable balance in pursuing its legitimate objective  
and s. 9 should be saved by s. 1 of the Charter”. In reaching this  
conclusion, he was influenced by three factors. First was his assessment  
that “in freezing wages of all public servants and at the same time  
implementing a refined Pay Equity Agreement, ... (t)he deferral of the  
retroactive benefits under the Pay Equity Agreement was reasonable in the  
circumstances”. Secondly, he took the view that “the impairment by s. 9" of  
the restraint legislation “of s. 15 of the Charter was done for a legitimate  
and pressing need of fiscal restraint ... not ... for an improper and colorable  
purpose”. Lastly, proportionality was respected by the legislation  
“eliminating the retroactive pay requirements and adopting a program for  
pay equity to continue and be implemented during a period of fiscal restraint  
that affected all public servants”.  
[49] Accordingly, the Government nominee embraced the view that s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation, whilst, infringing s. 15, was saved under s. 1 of the  
Charter. This being the case, he concluded s. 9 was valid and should be  
given effect. From this standpoint, Government’s nominee, contrary to the  
view of the other members of the Board, reasoned that NAPE’s grievance  
should be dismissed.  
Page: 17  
÷
the Board’s decision:  
[50] As will be apparent from the foregoing summaries of their decisions, each  
of the three Board members advanced substantial positions in addressing  
NAPE’s grievance. At this juncture, it is well to explain how the  
chairperson’s decision stands as that of the Board, and highlight points in it  
which, as will presently be seen, became subject to attack by both parties to  
this appeal in their respective applications for judicial review in the Trial  
Division.  
[51] The collective agreement contains a provision stipulating that the decision  
of the majority shall be the decision of the Board, and if there is no majority  
decision, the chairperson’s disposition shall stand as the Board’s decision.  
Despite the varying viewpoints expressed by the members occupied with  
NAPE’s grievance, however, the chairperson’s decision at bar does not have  
to rest upon a lack of a majority to be recognized as that of the Board. As  
the summaries of the results of the Board’s deliberations show, the  
chairperson’s decision received sufficient endorsements to be able to be  
regarded as commanding a majority in its result, and in the essential  
findings leading to it.  
[52] In the first place, there was unanimous agreement with the chairperson on  
the two preliminary issues of bias and jurisdiction. Government’s nominee  
explicitly sided with the chairperson in that regard. It is true that NAPE’s  
nominee to the Board made no expressed reference to these preliminary  
concerns, and focused virtually exclusively on his departure from the chair’s  
construction of s. 9's language. However, his expressed concurrence with  
the chair’s reasoning on the substantive constitutional issue, together with  
his agreement in the result of the award, leaves no room to infer that he took  
a different stance form the chairperson relating to the latter’s rulings that no  
apprehension of bias existed and the grievances were arbitrable.  
[53] With respect to the first of the two substantive issues, the Government’s  
nominee also agreed with the chairperson’s interpretation of s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation. As his concurrence was unqualified, it must be taken  
that he was in accord with the reasoning leading to that construction as well.  
As noted, the union nominee dissented from this aspect of the chair’s  
decision for reasons set out in the foregoing summary of the opinion of  
NAPE’s nominee. Accordingly, the union’s nominee was in the minority on  
that point, although associating with the result of the chair’s award.  
Page: 18  
[54] As to the second substantive issue, the chairperson’s conclusion of s. 9's  
violation of s. 15 of the Charter was unanimously concurred in by the other  
members. The Government’s concurrence was explicit. In the case of the  
union’s nominee, once again this may be inferred from his unqualified  
concurrence on the constitutional issue, which may be taken not only as  
endorsing the chair’s finding of a breach of s. 15, but as lending majority  
weight to the reasoning leading to it.  
[55] On the question of whether the s. 15 breach was redeemed through resort to  
s. 1 of the Charter, the union nominee’s unqualified concurrence also made  
the chairperson’s finding and reasoning in that regard that of the majority,  
and hence the decision of the Board. The Government nominee’s departure  
from that phase of the grievance resolution put his opinion in dissent.  
[56] In sum, therefore, the chairperson’s decision attracted sufficient support  
from his colleagues on the Board to render his direction that the employer  
“pay any compensation from the violation” of the Pay Equity Agreement the  
majority disposition, together with the reasoning that led him to that  
conclusion, either unanimous or majority determinations.  
[57] In the result, the chairperson’s decision became the appropriate focal point  
of the appellate attacks that were lodged against the Board’s reasoning by  
both parties to the arbitration.  
÷
attacks on Board’s decision:  
[58] The Board’s award, as expressed in its Chair’s decision, was attacked by  
both sides.  
[59] The Government applied to the Trial Division to have the award set aside.  
It first complained over the disposition of the two preliminary issues. Thus,  
it alleged error in the unanimous findings that there was no reasonable  
apprehension of bias resulting from the employment of the chairperson’s  
spouse in the public health care sector. It also maintained the Board erred in  
concluding it had jurisdiction to determine the constitutional validity of s. 9  
of the restraint legislation.  
[60] Whilst not challenging the majority interpretation that under s. 9 only the  
amount due on the first payment adjustment date fell due on April 1, 1993,  
the Government alleged error in the disposition of the second substantive  
issue. Thus, it maintains it was an error to have concluded both that s. 9  
infringes s. 15(1), and that the violation is not saved by s. 1 of the Charter.  
Page: 19  
[61] NAPE countered with its own application seeking to have the majority  
decision quashed. Its application primarily focuses upon the Board’s  
statutory interpretation taking issue with the majority’s construction of s. 9.  
Underscoring that in construing the effect of s-s. 9(3) as extinguishing the  
employer’s obligations to provide equity adjustments for the period from  
June 24, 1988 to March 31, 1991, by holding only the amount of the first  
equity adjustment payment was due on April 1, 1993, the Union claims this  
to be an erroneous interpretation. NAPE is thus maintaining the position of  
its nominee to the Board was correct i.e. that the full amount of the pay  
equity adjustments payable under the Pay Equity Agreement for the period  
from June 24, 1988 to March 31, 1991, had to be paid to affected employees  
on April 1, 1993, which, as preceding para. 10 notes, was when the restraint  
period expired.  
[62] NAPE also attacked the reliance that the majority had placed on Hansard in  
interpreting s. 9 of the restraint legislation. It further alleged in its  
application for review that the majority erred in treating pay equity  
adjustments for the period from June 24, 1998, to March 31,1991 to be  
retroactive. These two complaints also seek to have these findings  
supplanted by reiterating contrary positions articulated in the union  
nominee’s decision.  
[63] It is against the foregoing background that both the Government’s  
application and NAPE’s cross-application for judicial review of the  
arbitration decision were argued before a judge in the Trial Division. As the  
preceding account explains, the upshot of the two applications was to call  
into question all of the Board’s rulings. Government took issue with the  
Board’s disposition of the preliminary bias and jurisdictional issues, and  
with the Charter resolution, whilst NAPE took exception with the Board’s  
statutory interpretation as well as its reliance on Hansard and its perceived  
treating as retroactive the equity adjustments subsequent to the entry into  
the Pay Equity Agreement. This judgement now turns to the judge’s  
disposition of all of the challenges to the complaints registered against the  
Arbitration Board’s decision.  
The Trial Division’s decision  
[64] The judge at first instance addressed the complaints against the Arbitration  
Board’s decision in the order presented by the application and cross-  
Page: 20  
application. The resumé of his decision will now summarize the judge’s  
findings on the issues in the order in which he treated them.  
÷
the jurisdiction issue:  
[65] The judge first addressed the preliminary question of whether the Board had  
jurisdiction to determine the constitutionality of s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation. In so doing, he was inquiring into the sustainability of the  
Board’s unanimous finding that NAPE’s grievance was arbitrable. He  
concluded that the Board lacked jurisdiction, whilst holding that its decision  
should be set aside on that account alone.  
[66] In his reasoning leading to that conclusion, the judge defined the issue to be  
“whether an arbitration board may determine a constitutional question  
arising from the Charter”. In analysing that question the judge referred to  
existing authorities. In so doing, he underscored the statement in Chuddy  
Chicks Ltd. v. Ontario Labour Relations Board, [1991] 2 S.C.R. 5 at p.  
14 where La Forest J. declared that an administrative body must have  
jurisdiction over “the parties, subject matter and remedy sought” in order to  
be considered empowered to arbitrate any issue before it. As the text of Mr.  
Justice La Forest’s declaration indicates, an arbitration board may be  
considered an administrative body for the purpose of this jurisdictional  
discussion.  
[67] The decision now under appeal went on to maintain the response to the  
stated issue of an arbitration board’s competence to decide a Charter  
question hinged upon “whether the dispute between the parties arose under  
or out of the interpretation, administration or violation of the Collective  
Agreement ...”. In other words, the judge’s assessment of the Board’s  
arbitrability holding focused on whether it had had jurisdiction over the  
subject matter. It has been accepted as common ground throughout these  
proceedings that the Board had jurisdiction over the parties. In view of his  
finding on the Board’s lack of jurisdiction over the subject matter, the judge  
who delivered the decision now under scrutiny found it unnecessary to  
address its power over the remedy sought.  
[68] In his discussion of whether the dispute arose out of the collective  
agreement, the judge observed that Government had clearly “refused to  
honour its obligation to make pay equity wage adjustments for the years  
prior to the 1991 fiscal year”, as it had undertaken to do in its agreement  
that had become part of its subsisting collective agreements affected by the  
Page: 21  
arbitration. Instead, Government was relying on direction in the restraint  
legislation to “implement pay equity adjustments in accordance with Section  
9 ...”. This, the judge wrote, engaged inquiry into “whether Section 9 of the  
Act deferred implementation of the Pay Equity Agreement as contended by  
Government”.  
[69] While noting that that inquiry “is a matter of statutory interpretation”, which  
he was subsequently to address in dealing with NAPE’s cross-application,  
the judge stated the “core dispute before the Board obviously was whether  
Section 9 of the Act violated Section 15(1) of the Charter, and, if so,  
whether it was justifiable under Section 1 of the Charter”. Then, the  
impugned decision notes that the evidence before the Board “focused on  
that issue” of s. 9's constitutionality, whilst “the Union’s real dispute”  
related to interpretation of the restraint legislation. Thus, the judge stated  
that NAPE’s grievance was essentially “with the legislature, not with the  
executive which did not have the option of disregarding the will of the  
legislature as expressed in the Act”. From this standpoint the judge ruled:  
C
[33] ... The dispute did not arise either expressly or inferentially from  
the Collective Agreement. The dispute was over the constitutional  
validity of Section 9 of the Act.  
C
[34] As the dispute does not arise from the Collective Agreement, the  
Board did not have jurisdiction to determine the constitutional  
validity of the Act.  
[70] As already mentioned, the judge recognized this conclusion, in itself, was  
sufficient to set aside the decision of the Board. Despite declining to  
address the Board’s jurisdiction over the remedy sought in light of this  
finding that the dispute did not arise out of the Collective Agreement, he did  
not terminate his decision at this juncture, but proceeded to address the  
other exceptions taken by the parties with the Board’s decision.  
÷
the bias issue:  
[71] Hence, the judge next took up the second preliminary issue that also had  
been unanimously dismissed by the Board, i.e. Government’s complaint that  
the chairperson should be disqualified because a reasonable apprehension of  
bias existed, stemming from the chairperson’s spouse being a member of the  
nurse’s union and her employment in the public health sector. For reasons  
that will later be touched upon when this judgment addresses his holding,  
Page: 22  
the judge concluded that in the circumstances obtaining there was no ground  
to reasonably apprehend bias.  
÷
the constitutionality issue:  
>
the Charter breach:  
[72] In broaching the substantive issues beyond those two preliminary ones, the  
judge first addressed the constitutionality of s. 9 of the restraint legislation.  
It will be noted that this was in inverse order to the chairperson’s treatment  
of considering firstly the questions respecting the construction of s. 9.  
Presumably this change stems from the fact that that question was next  
raised in the Government’s application for judicial review, and the issue of  
the Board’s statutory interpretation was not contested by Government, but  
was left to NAPE which raised it in its cross-appeal in the Trial Division.  
[73] The Board’s unanimous opinion that a violation of equality rights  
guaranteed under the Charter had been perpetrated through the enactment  
of s. 9 of the restraint legislation was contested by Government in the  
judicial review hearing. The judge noted that the decision of the Board’s  
chairperson records that an attempt had been made in the Government’s  
argument in the arbitration hearing to depict the effect of s. 9 as “merely the  
substitution of one process for another which does not infringe s. 15(1) of  
the Charter”.  
[74] Whilst endorsing the Board’s rejection of that contention, the judge first  
quotes from the Board’s treatment of the issue of s. 9's constitutional  
validity wherein the chairperson reasoned:  
C
... once government entered into the Pay Equity Agreement to address  
what it agreed was a discriminatory practice, it could not, without  
infringing s. 15(1), revoke or make unlawful a right or privilege that  
would affect or have an adverse impact on individuals of a particular  
gender. In passing s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act,  
government knew it would have an adverse impact on “employees in  
female dominated classes within the various bargaining units.”  
... here the legislation does not seek to remedy inequality but to  
curtail and postpone entitlement to equal pay for female employees  
even though government has agreed that wage adjustments are  
necessary.  
C
Page: 23  
[75] Then, in rejecting Government’s submission of benign constitutional effect,  
the judge’s decision reads:  
C
[55] ... The effect of s. 9 was obvious - it postponed the achievement  
of pay equity thereby ensuring that the affected employees - i.e. those  
in female dominated classes - would not receive the incremental pay  
adjustments for the 1988-1990 fiscal years to which they were  
entitled under the Pay Equity Agreement. Section 9 had an adverse  
economic impact upon a class of employees which Government had  
recognized as the victims of systemic gender discrimination.  
>
the s. 1 analysis:  
[76] Having found that s. 9 of the legislation breached the constitutionally  
guaranteed equality rights, the judge turned to inquire whether the  
legislation provision was yet saved under s. 1 of the Charter. He  
conducted this inquiry in the context of the four criteria for justification  
under s. 1 that were enunciated in Oakes.  
[77] As to the sufficiently important objective test, the judge took no exception  
with the opinion that had been unanimously endorsed by the members of the  
Board that s. 9 met the test. Stating it had been established that  
“Government faced a severe financial situation in early 1991, which  
required prompt and drastic action”, he described s. 9's “objective of  
deferring implementation of pay equity thereby considerably reducing  
government expenditures” as a “major part of Government’s response to its  
fiscal problems”. Given “these severe fiscal circumstances”, he held “the  
objective of reducing expenditures was sufficiently important to justify a  
limitation on the s. 15(1) Charter rights”.  
[78] With respect to the second criterion enunciated in Oakes, quoting from the  
Board’s majority view that s. 9 of the restraint legislation was “well tailored  
to suit” its purpose, and from the Government nominee’s view in similar  
vein, the judge, after noting that that provision had the “effect of eliminating  
the payment of pay equity adjustments for the 1988-1990 fiscal years”,  
concurred with the unanimous conclusion reached by the Board that the test  
of rational connection to the objective had been met.  
[79] The judge, however, did not share the majority view that the third criterion  
of minimal impairment had not been met. After referring in some detail to  
the Board’s disposition rendered through the chairperson’s decision, and  
making detailed references to applicable legal principles enunciated by the  
Page: 24  
authorities, the judge stated his objection to this aspect of the Board’s  
decision to be that:  
C
[91] ... it overlooks the extended budgetary explanation given by the  
Minister. The Minister had earlier explained that Government was  
faced with a 200 million dollar deficit which was threatening to  
escalate. The limits of Government borrowing were explored and tax  
increases were decided upon. Expenditure reductions were examined  
and had to emphasize the salary and compensation component which  
represented approximately 70% of provincial expenditures, apart  
from social assistance payments and debt service payments. That is  
apparent from the evidence of R. Smart, p. 69* and from the budget  
excerpts which were before the Board and which were obviously  
known to all members of the legislature. The Minister stated that to  
achieve the required expenditure reductions Government considered  
the general wage freeze and deferral of pay equity adjustment  
payments to advert the possibility of mass layoffs with a consequent  
drastic effect on Government services. In introducing the legislation  
the Minister addressed its affect upon the Pay Equity Agreement. In  
summary the twenty-four million dollars saved by the deferral of the  
pay equity adjustments was part of a larger two hundred million  
dollar fiscal problem. To address that problem Government had  
considered various alternatives such as borrowing, tax increases,  
budget freezes and reductions in Government expenditures.  
*[referral is to transcript of evidence before the Board and the  
testimony provided to it by the Assistant Secretary of Treasury Board  
- Human Resources].  
C
[80] The foregoing provides the gist of the rationale of the decision under appeal  
for viewing as flawed the reasons for the Board having concluded that s. 9  
of the restraint legislation fell short of meeting the minimal impairment test.  
The chairperson, the judge concluded, erred in his appreciation of the  
evidence in proceeding on the footing that solely the lay-off of  
approximately 900 employees had been considered as an alternative to the  
infringement effected through s. 9 of the restraint legislation.  
[81] The judge cited a second error by the Board in its improper use of  
“suggestions made by the Opposition in the legislative debate ...”. He  
expressed doubt as to the relevancy attributed in the Board’s decision to the  
test of different restraint measures invoked in 1994, as well as the  
Page: 25  
continuance of “step increases and reclassifications” under s. 9, which had  
also been mentioned as indicia that less restrictive measures were available  
which would have minimized the infringement of the Charter equality  
rights.  
[82] In the result, the judge, contrary to the conclusion of the Board’s majority,  
and in substantial agreement with the Government nominee’s assessment of  
the legislation’s conformity with the minimal impairment criterion, held:  
C
[98] ... from the evidence before the Board ... that the Legislature,  
faced with difficult financial circumstances, made a reasonable effort  
to minimize the infringement of the Section 15(1) Charter right when  
it chose, in Section 9 of the Act, to delay implementation of the Pay  
Equity Agreement”.  
[83] In addressing the fourth test of proportionate effect the judge applied the  
same standard as had the Board’s chairperson of inquiring whether the  
violation of the equality rights entrenched in s. 15 of the Charter was “too  
high a price to pay” for the benefit of attaining the restraint legislation’s  
objective embodied in s. 9 of the Act. In the course of his reasoning the  
judge acknowledged the union had mounted “a powerful argument against  
an incremental approach to pay equity” that was reflected in the posited  
unacceptable premise inherent in the impugned pay equity restraints which  
perpetrated “arbitrary distinctions based on gender” as “a legitimate basis  
for imposing negative consequences, particularly when the economy is  
failing”.  
[84] However, endorsing the premise that “Legislatures should not be obliged to  
deal with all aspects of a problem at once”, but “must surely be permitted to  
take incremental measures”, the judge endorsed the viewpoint that  
“reasonable leeway” must be given “to take into account difficulties ... that  
would arise if it attempted to deal with social and economic problems in  
their entirety, assuming such problems can ever be perceived in their  
entirety”. From that standpoint, the judge found that s. 9's restraint on pay  
equity payments met the proportionality criterion laid down in Oakes. He  
explained his stance as follows:  
C
[104] The Charter infringement in this case was the legislated delay  
in the incremental process from April 1, 1988, to April 1, 1991, which  
had an adverse impact upon those entitled to pay adjustments,  
particularly those who left the work force prior to the postponed  
achievement of pay equity. The benefit of Section 9 of the Act, being  
Page: 26  
the financial saving, accrued to the public treasury when it faced a  
severe fiscal problem.  
C
[105] Having concluded that the objective was sufficiently important  
and that there had been a reasonable effort to minimize the  
infringement of the Charter right it follows, in my view, that the law  
did not have a disproportionately severe effect upon the affected  
group.  
>
the constitutional rulings:  
[85] There were actually two arms to the judge’s advertence to the  
constitutionality issue raised before him. The first culminated in his ruling  
on the preliminary jurisdictional challenge pursued before him by  
Government. As earlier noted, for reasons summarized in preceding paras.  
65 to 69, he ruled the Board did not have jurisdiction to determine the  
constitutional validity of the restraint legislation because the dispute’s  
subject matter was over the constitutional validity of s. 9 of the legislation,  
and did not rise from the Collective Agreement. Secondly, having reasoned  
as just recounted in preceding paras. 76 to 84, that the four criteria for  
application of s. 1 of the Charter laid down in Oakes had been met, the  
judge held that s. 9 of the restraint legislation prescribed reasonable limits  
on the affected s. 15 Charter rights which are justifiable in a free and  
democratic society within the intent of s. 1 of the Charter. Having made  
that ruling, he ended his treatment of the constitutional aspect of the  
application before him with an order expressed as follows:  
C
C
[106] It is ordered that  
(a) The decision of the Board be set aside on the grounds that it  
did not have jurisdiction to determine the constitutional validity  
of Section 9 of the Act.  
C
(b) In the alternative the decision of the Board be set aside on the  
grounds that it erred in law in finding that the infringement of  
Section 15(1) of the Charter was not saved under Section 1 of  
the Charter.  
C
(c) That the Applicant have its costs.  
[86] Normally, such directions setting aside a decision under review and  
providing responsibility for costs would be expected to be reserved for the  
end of the reviewing disposition. Such is not the case here, however, as the  
judge’s reasoning continues with his interpretation of the effect of s. 9 of the  
Page: 27  
restraint legislation which centered on s. 9's impact upon the obligations  
undertaken in the Pay Equity Agreement. While at first glance this  
continued addressing of the merits of the Arbitration Board’s decision might  
seem yet another complexity in the already intricate circumstances with  
which this appeal must grapple, it nonetheless has a logical explanation.  
[87] The explanation lies in the fact that the judge addressed the issues before  
him by first taking up those raised in the Government’s application for  
review of the arbitration award prior to turning to those put forth in NAPE’s  
motion to quash it. This resulted in the constitutionality of the legislation,  
which had been raised by Government, being addressed before the union’s  
complaint that error was present in the Board’s statutory interpretation,  
which it had raised through its cross-application. As already noted, this  
approach was inverse to that adopted by the Board with respect to the two  
substantive issues raised in these proceedings, which first addressed the  
effect of the legislation’s language prior to determining whether the  
wording of s. 9 met constitutional muster and could be given its effect.  
[88] While the explanation is a simple logistical one, it nonetheless needs be  
acknowledged that a certain incongruity might nonetheless be perceived on  
its face with a decision being set aside at a point some eighty percent  
through the reviewing disposition, where the residue proceeds to continue to  
discuss its merits. While the rationale for the situation is understandable, it  
is apparent that the judge did not intend to “set aside” the Board’s decision  
at that point. Instead he obviously had to be setting aside the Board’s two  
rulings that the constitutional validity of s. 9 of the legislation was  
arbitrable, and that s. 9 was unable to withstand Charter scrutiny. Having  
found the constitutional validity of s. 9 was not arbitrable for want of  
jurisdiction in the Board, and that the breach of equality rights perpetrated  
by s. 9 was saved by s. 1 of the Charter in any event, it was logical that the  
decision should pass to inquire whether s. 9 could be construed, as did the  
Board, to have extinguished the employer’s obligation to make the pay  
equity payments for the period from June 24, 1988, to March 31, 1991,  
which the Union in its application for judicial review claimed to be due on  
expiry of the legislated restraint period.  
[89] Having put the impugned decision’s constitutional rulings in their true  
perspective, attention will now focus on the judge’s treatment of the  
substantive statutory interpretation issue, and the other issues raised in  
NAPE’s cross-application for review of the Board’s decision.  
Page: 28  
÷
the statutory interpretation issue:  
[90] The judge posed two questions for analysis of the dispute relating to the  
statutory interpretation of s. 9. Firstly, he addressed whether the language  
of the restraint legislation extinguished “Government’s obligation to pay  
pay equity wage adjustments for the period June 24, 1988, to March 31,  
1991". Secondly, in the alternative, and in the same context of the  
legislation’s language, he explored whether Government was required to  
pay, effective April 1, 1991, “the wage rate due in the fourth year of the Pay  
Equity Agreement”.  
>
the extinguishment question:  
[91] The judge opened his discussion of the extinguishment question by noting it  
was common ground, and “(neither) Government nor the Union disputed”  
the conclusion, that s-s. 9(1)’s preclusion of “a provision which implements  
that pay equity agreement retroactivity” effectively foreclosed payments of  
pay equity prior to June 24, 1988, when the Pay Equity Agreement was  
executed. To this extent, therefore, the judge was pointing out that no  
exception was taken with the conclusion that s. 9 should be construed as  
extinguishing rights to accruing pay equity adjustments prior to the  
Agreement’s entry. It is noteworthy that this general acceptance is  
consonant with the Board’s stance, expressed in the chairperson’s position  
recounted in preceding para. 20, that, recognizing retroactive provisions as  
those made operative prior to a contract’s entry, the effect of s-s. 9(1) and s-  
s. 9(2) “is to eliminate the retroactive period prior to June 24, 1988".  
[92] As had the Board before him, therefore, the judge’s attention focused upon  
whether s. 9 had the further effect of extinguishing Government obligations  
after the date of entry into the Pay Equity Agreement on June 24, 1988, up  
to the end of the restraint period on March 31, 199l. Here, as had been the  
case in the arbitration proceedings, concentration centered on s-s. 9(3).  
[93] The judge proceeded on the footing that the effect of s-s. 9(3) upon  
adjustments payable in the Pay Equity Agreement’s currency subsequent to  
its entry turned on the merit of NAPE’s submission:  
C
[111] ... that Section 9 of the Act is not ambiguous and gives only one  
reasonable meaning, namely: “The date when ‘the pay equity  
adjustment is agreed upon’ in subsection 9(3) is the date when the  
Page: 29  
commitment to institute pay equity was reached, not the date when  
the specific amount was determined”.  
[94] It should be observed that this submission puts the statutory interpretation  
of s. 9 in a nutshell insofar as the inquiry into its effect upon wage equity  
payments under the Pay Equity Agreement is concerned. The policy of the  
legislation was not to preclude altogether pay equity agreements, but to  
prescribe when pay equity wage adjustments could begin, regardless of what  
might be otherwise provided in that regard. Commencement of such  
payment was restricted under s-s. 9(3) to “the date on which the pay equity  
adjustment is agreed upon”. Because that legislative provision came into  
force with effect from March 31, 1991, it thereby caught within its ambit the  
Pay Equity Agreement which, while negotiated, could not be implemented  
before receipt in July of 1991 by the Steering Committee of the financial  
consultants’ report on the quantum of wage adjustment committed under the  
Agreement.  
[95] Interpretation of the highlighted phrase of s-s. 9(3) was key to resolution of  
the issue as to whether those words of limitation eliminated the obligation  
undertaken by Government in the Agreement to make payments between its  
entry and the end of the restraint period. If, as NAPE submitted, and its  
nominee to the board concluded, “the date on which the pay equity wage  
adjustment is agreed upon” is “the date when the commitment to institute  
pay equity was reached”, then this was June 24, 1988, and s-s. 9(3) must be  
construed as permitting, and not eliminating, the obligation of Government  
to make pay adjustments from that date. On the other hand, if as  
Government maintained, and the Board’s majority concluded, the date  
contemplated by s-s. 9(3)’s wording was “when the specific amount was  
determined”, then the highlighted phrase must be taken as eliminating  
Government’s obligation to make payment during the residue of the  
restraint period, i.e. until after March 31, 1991, because the quantum of the  
wage adjustment could not have been determined until after receipt of the  
report in July of 1991.  
[96] The judge sided with the majority’s interpretation, stating that “(a) careful  
reading of Section 9(3) in my view can lead to no other conclusion than the  
one reached by the Board”. Elaborating on this conclusion he reasoned:  
C
[115] The interpretation advanced by the Union essentially reads “the  
pay equity wage adjustment” in the last line as if it read “pay equity”  
Page: 30  
without attributing any consequence to the words “wage adjustment”.  
However, meaning should be given to all words of the legislative text.  
[97] The judge then proceeded to attribute consequence to the words he said  
NAPE had ignored by resorting to the Oxford Dictionary’s definition of  
“adjustment” as “a settlement of a share in respect of a payment”. From this  
he went on to reason that “wage adjustment” in the context of s-s. 9(3)  
“means the settlement, or ascertainment, of an amount of wages”. It  
followed, he concluded, “that ‘pay equity wage adjustment’ refers to the  
settlement of the amount of wages payable in respect of pay equity”. Here,  
the judge was in obvious disagreement with the position of NAPE’s  
nominee, recounted in preceding para. 41, that the critical phrase in s-s. 9(3)  
did not speak of the date “upon which the amount of the pay equity  
adjustment is determined” but rather when “the parties agreed to the pay  
adjustment itself”.  
[98] The impugned decision then goes on to discuss the context within which the  
restraint legislation was enacted and its purpose, whilst further testing the  
judge’s reasoning for agreeing with the Board’s construction of s-s. 9(3).  
The judge ended his analysis by concluding the restraint legislation, “and  
particularly Section 9 thereof, clearly extinguished Government’s obligation  
to make pay equity wage adjustments for the period prior to the date when  
the adjustments were agreed upon”. As explained, he defined this date as  
when the specific amount of the adjustments were agreed upon in July of  
1991.  
>
the alternate issue:  
[99] The judge then explored the validity of NAPE’s alternate position on  
statutory interpretation which is recounted in preceding paras. 42 and 43.  
After quoting from the relevant passage from the decision of the Union’s  
nominee to the Board, the judge stated there were two aspects to NAPE’s  
submission that its nominee was correct in holding the balance of the pay  
equity adjustment was “payable in accordance with the Pay Equity  
Agreement” on April 1, 1992. The first emerges from the legislation, and  
the second from Article 4.01 of the Collective Agreement. In regard to the  
legislation, the judge noted he had already concluded the language of s. 9  
must be read in the context of the Pay Equity Agreement. Then, after  
pointing out that each contemplates an “incremental approach to the  
achievement of pay equity”, he reasons that the effect of s-s. 9(3) on the Pay  
Page: 31  
Equity Agreement “was to replace April 1, 1988, being the first pay equity  
adjustment date prescribed under the Agreement”. However, that was the  
only change, so that the remaining language in the Agreement was  
unaffected. This, in the judge’s view, resulted in the adjustments having to  
be paid incrementally after the pay equity wage adjustment was agreed  
upon, “within the five year period provided stipulated” in the Agreement.  
The full entitlement that would have accrued, but for the legislated  
restraints, during the period of awaiting finalization of its calculation by the  
financial consultants was not payable, therefore, as NAPE’s nominee held it  
to be, under this reasoning of the judge. Instead, in his estimation, the  
schedule for commencement of the incremental payments was shifted under  
the legislation.  
[100] With respect to the Agreement, and the construction of Article 4.01 by  
NAPE’s nominee, the judge acknowledged that the Article expressed its  
parties’ purpose of eliminating discrimination by reason of sex. However,  
he underscores the Agreement also sets out the intended mechanism for  
attaining this objective. Then, he points out that it “established a highly  
structured procedure to redress systemic gender discrimination culminating  
in payment of wage adjustments up to a maximum of 1% per year of payroll  
with the proviso that pay equity was to be achieved no later than the fifth  
fiscal year”. For NAPE to maintain that its nominee was correct in  
contending “the full amount of the adjustments became immediately payable  
when ascertained”, the judge held, was to deny the validity of the language  
in the Agreement.  
>
reliance on Hansard:  
[101] In response to NAPE’s attack on the Board’s use of Hansard, the judge  
stated that a full review of the Board’s decision led him to conclude its use  
was “not critical” and the Board’s interpretation of s. 9 should not be set  
aside on that account. Moreover, he stated, it was unclear that the reference  
to Hansard was to interpret s. 9, but “it is equally arguable” it “was to  
establish the context of the legislation”.  
[102] As a result of his findings on these three issues raised by it, the judge  
dismissed the cross-application.  
Result of appealed decision  
Page: 32  
[103] To recapitulate, the decision now under appellate scrutiny overturned the  
Board’s decision that it had jurisdiction to determine the constitutional  
validity of the restraint legislation. However, it concurred with the other  
unanimous disposition of the second preliminary issue, which held there  
was no reasonable apprehension of bias warranting the chairperson’s  
disqualification.  
[104] The appealed decision agreed with the majority Board finding regarding the  
statutory interpretation of s. 9, whilst dismissing NAPE’s contention that the  
majority misconstrued that provision’s effect. While it shared the Board’s  
unanimous view that s. 9 infringed s. 15 of the Charter, it held the majority  
erred in finding the violation was not saved under s. 1 of the Charter.  
[105] The upshot of these findings was that the Board’s decision allowing  
NAPE’s grievance was overturned. NAPE is now appealing that  
determination seeking to have the judge’s decision overturned and the  
decision the Board’s majority upheld insofar as it deals with jurisdiction and  
s. 1 of the Charter, but:  
C
... set aside and remitted back to the Board for reconsideration on the  
issues relating to the effect of the Public Sector Restraint Act on the  
Government’s obligation to provide pay equity adjustments as  
provided for in the Pay Equity Agreement, on the Government’s  
failure on April 1, 1993 to pay the wage rate due in the fourth year of  
the Pay Equity Agreement, and with the direction from this  
Honourable Court that it is improper to rely on Hansard in statutory  
interpretation ....  
It will be apparent from this exception to the Board disposition that NAPE seeks  
in the appeal at bar to reinstate the Board’s decision in all respects save in regard  
to the issues taken with it in its cross-application that was dismissed at first  
instance.  
[106] For its part, Government counters with a cross-appeal. In it Government  
maintains the appealed decision erred in holding the Arbitration Board was  
correct in finding s. 9 of the restraint legislation infringes the equality rights  
guaranteed under s. 15 of the Charter. The cross-appeal also claims error  
in the appealed decision’s upholding of the Board’s finding that there was  
no reasonable apprehension of bias resulting from the employment of the  
chairperson’s spouse.  
Page: 33  
[107] In the result, Government’s position was to agree with the judge on his key  
findings that the Arbitration Board had no jurisdiction to determine the  
constitutional validity of s. 9, and that the infringement of s. 15 was not  
saved, in any event, under s. 1 of the Charter. Through the cross-appeal, it  
maintains the Board’s disposition was vitiated on the preliminary bias  
challenge, and challenges that s. 9 even violated the s. 15 equality Charter  
rights in the first place.  
Issues in this appeal  
[108] From the preceding outline of the formal grounds of appeal, it can be seen  
that all issues argued before the judge at first instance are re-presented by  
one party or the other for reconsideration by this Court. Accordingly, there  
were seven issues in all argued in this appeal. Five were raised by NAPE in  
its challenge of the judge’s decision, and the remaining two by Government  
in its cross-appeal. They were defined by the parties to be whether the  
decision under appeal erred:  
C
C
(i)  
in holding the Board lacked jurisdiction to hear the grievances;  
(ii) in finding that s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act  
infringes s. 15(1) of the Charter;  
C
C
(iii) in holding the violation of s. 15(1) of the Charter was saved  
under s. 1 of the Charter;  
(iv) in agreeing with the Board’s conclusion that s-s. 9(3) of the  
restraint legislation extinguished Government’s obligation in  
the Pay Equity Agreement to provide pay equity adjustments  
for the period from April 1, 1988 to March 31, 1991;  
(v) in agreeing with the Board’s conclusion that Government was  
not required to pay the wage rate due in the fourth year of the  
Pay Equity Agreement;  
C
C
C
(vi) in concluding the Board made no error in referring to Hansard  
in its interpretation of s. 9 of the restraint legislation; and,  
(vii) in finding there was no reasonable apprehension of bias on the  
part of the Chair from the employment of the Chair’s spouse.  
It is noted that the second and last in the above list of issues were raised in  
Government’s cross-appeal and that the last one, dealing with the bias issue, was  
addressed by the judge immediately after the jurisdiction issue which, along with  
bias, had been raised as preliminary concerns. However, for reasons which will be  
Page: 34  
explained when the bias issue is taken up, although dealt with as a preliminary  
issue in both former proceedings leading up to this appeal, these issues are posed  
in logical sequential order that best lends itself to efficient treatment of the merits  
of this appeal. Accordingly, the bias issue is listed last in the foregoing format  
for analysis of the challenges taken against the decision under appeal.  
The jurisdictional issue:  
÷
jurisdictional bases:  
[109] The starting point in the discussion of NAPE’s complaint alleging the judge  
erred in holding the Arbitration Board lacked jurisdiction to have heard the  
representative grievance is the statement of La Forest J. in Chuddy Chicks  
which, as preceding para. 66 has already noted, the judge has highlighted as  
articulating the bases of an administrative tribunal’s jurisdiction to  
determine Charter questions. Thus, at p. 14 of Chuddy Chicks La Forest  
J. had the following to say on that subject:  
C
... jurisdiction must have expressly or impliedly been conferred on the  
tribunal by its enabling statute or otherwise. This fundamental  
principle holds true regardless of the nature of the issue before the  
administrative body. Thus, a tribunal prepared to address a Charter  
issue must already have jurisdiction over the whole of the matter  
before it, namely, the parties, subject matter and remedy sought.  
[110] No exception is taken in this appeal with the judge’s reliance on the  
foregoing authority’s asserted legal bases of an administrative tribunal’s  
jurisdiction over “the whole of the matter before it” regardless “of the nature  
of the issue before the administrative body”. As the above passage states,  
this jurisdictional reach is specifically expressed to include competence to  
address the impact of the Charter issues on “the whole of the matter before  
it”. No objection could be taken to that reliance in view of the acceptance  
of the Supreme Court of Canada, through the majority judgment of La  
Forest J. in Chuddy Chicks, of the three asserted bases of jurisdiction as  
“fundamental principle”.  
[111] As already noted in preceding para. 67, it has been accepted throughout  
these proceedings that the Board has jurisdiction over the parties. The bone  
of contention here is whether it also had jurisdiction over the subject matter  
and remedy. Attention will now focus on these questions.  
Page: 35  
÷
the subject matter:  
the approach:  
>
[112] There are two touch-stone cases of particular note which were cited by  
counsel for NAPE as the backdrop to her submissions put forth in support of  
her contention that the judge erred in holding, as earlier recorded in  
preceding para. 69, that the subject matter of “(t)he dispute did not arise  
either expressly or inferentially from the Collective Agreement”, and thus  
“the Board did not have jurisdiction to determine the constitutional validity  
of the Act”. The first is St. Anne Nackawic Pulp and Paper v. CPU,  
[1986] 1 S.C.R. 704, and the second, Weber v. Ontario Hydro, [1995] 2  
S.C.R. 929.  
[113] In the frequently quoted St. Anne Nackawic, the Supreme Court of Canada  
addressed for the first time, as p. 708 of that authority records, “... whether  
a court of otherwise competent jurisdiction is authorized to receive a claim  
by an employer for damages against a trade union ... by reason of a strike”,  
which was apparently an illegal strike under the applicable labour  
legislation, and “at the same time a breach of the collective agreement  
between the employer and the Union”. The Supreme Court held at p. 731 in  
St. Anne Nackawic that the court was without jurisdiction to hear the  
dispute, and the “claim for damages must be advanced in the contractual  
forum of an arbitration board” which had exclusive jurisdiction at first  
instance over the matter. NAPE’s counsel opens her argument, in challenge  
of the judge’s holding that the Arbitration Board in the case at bar was  
bereft of jurisdiction, by quoting Estey J., the author of the unanimous  
judgment in St. Anne Nackawic, who held at p. 720 that a general  
consensus was apparent from a survey of authorities that:  
C
(t)he courts have no jurisdiction to consider claims arising out of  
rights created by a collective agreement.  
It follows as incidental corollary from this holding of Estey J. in St. Anne  
Nackawic that the jurisdiction lacking in the courts is vested in arbitration boards,  
and that its decision-making authority encompasses “claims arising out of rights  
created by a collective agreement”. It is such claims, therefore, which fall within  
the exclusive domain of the arbitration process.  
Page: 36  
[114] Counsel for NAPE enlists Weber to underscore two important points  
bearing on the determinations when claims “out of rights created by a  
collective agreement” arise, thereby demarcating the line defined in St.  
Anne Nackawic between arbitral and judicial jurisdiction over the subject  
matter of a dispute. The first point underscores that attention should focus  
on the facts of the dispute, rather than the legal issues it engages. Weber  
involved a tort in trespass allegedly committed by an employer by entry of  
its agent into the home of an employee. The court action taken by the  
employee against the employer was held barred by a majority in Weber  
because the subject matter of the dispute fell within the exclusive  
jurisdictional purview of the arbitration process, the differences between the  
parties having arisen from a collective agreement. Hence, the upshot of  
Weber was that redress had to be sought in the arbitral forum. In that  
authority, McLachlin J., the majority judgment’s author, provides the  
following direction in para. 43 respecting the focus on the subject matter of  
the dispute in addressing the proper jurisdictional forum at first instance for  
resolution of differences:  
C
Underlying ... St. Anne Nackawic is the insistence that the analysis of  
whether a matter falls within the exclusive arbitration clause must  
proceed on the basis of the facts surrounding the dispute between the  
parties, not on the basis of the legal issues which may be framed. The  
issue is not whether the action defined legally, is independent of the  
collective agreement, but rather whether the dispute is one “arising  
under [the] collective agreement”. Where the dispute, regardless of  
how it may be characterized legally, arises under the collective  
agreement, then the jurisdiction to resolve it lies exclusively with the  
labour tribunal and the courts cannot try it.  
[115] The second point made in Weber is the “essential character” test which it  
identified as the means of determining if the subject matter of the dispute is  
one “arising under [the] collective agreement”, and thus lies within the  
exclusive arbitral purview of an arbitration tribunal. Thus, in para. 52 of  
Weber, McLachlin J. went on to write:  
C
In considering the dispute, the decision-maker must attempt to define  
its “essential character”, to use the phrase of La Forest JA in Energy  
& Chemical Workers Union, Local 691 v. Irving Oil Ltd. (1983), 148  
D.L.R. (3d) 398 (N.B.C.A.).... In the majority of cases the nature of  
the dispute will be clear; either it had to do with the collective  
Page: 37  
agreement or it did not. Some cases, however, may be less than  
obvious. The question in each case is whether the dispute, in its  
essential character, arises from the interpretation, application,  
administration or violation of the collective agreement.  
[116] On the basis of the foregoing authoritative directions, this judgment will  
address the merits of NAPE’s contention that its grievances over  
Government’s failure to pay the retroactive wage adjustments, as  
undertaken in the pay equity addenda incorporated into the health care  
section collective agreements, came within the purview of the Arbitration  
Board’s jurisdiction by inquiry into whether the dispute over that failure is  
one arising under the collective agreements. If the “essential character” of  
that dispute “arises from the interpretation, application, administration or  
violation” of these agreements, then the subject matter of the dispute falls  
within the ambit of those agreements, and the judge’s conclusion that the  
Board lacked jurisdiction over the subject matter of the dispute, thereby  
disabling it from hearing the grievances, will have to be held incorrect. If it  
did not so arise, then the judge’s conclusion will have to be upheld.  
Page: 38  
>
NAPE’s position:  
[117] The Union maintains the Board was correct in assuming jurisdiction over  
the subject matter of the dispute, and the judge was wrong in his conclusion  
that it lacked jurisdiction to hear the grievances.  
[118] NAPE’s counsel argues the starting point of inquiry into jurisdiction over  
the subject matter is the grievance form. As preceding para. 13 recounts,  
the grievances seek “(f)ull redress” from Government’s failure to pay the  
retroactive “wage adjustments in accordance with the Pay Equity provisions  
of all Collective Agreements” together with interest thereon. As such,  
counsel insists, it is like many grievances arising out of collective  
agreements in that its subject matter is money. Every court, she maintains,  
agrees, where provision for money is made under collective agreements, that  
disputes over entitlement to that money lie within the exclusive jurisdiction  
of the arbitration process.  
[119] NAPE’s counsel also points out the essence of the judge’s jurisdictional  
decision rested on his reasoning, as preceding para. 69 confirms, that the  
“core dispute” arose over the constitutional validity of s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation which the Board had no jurisdiction to determine. In this regard,  
she also directs attention to the judge’s statement that NAPE’s “real  
dispute” is with the interpretation of s. 9. Thus, she underscores, the judge  
proceeded on the footing that the dispute arose over that provision in the  
restraint enactment, be it the provision’s constitutionality or construction,  
and not under the collective agreement over which the Board would have  
jurisdiction. Counsel argues this reasoning for ascribing a lack of  
jurisdiction in the Board is based on the absence of, or restricted, arbitral  
power to decide questions of law engaging constitutional analysis or  
ordinary statutory interpretation. This premise, she insists, whilst citing  
cases supporting her contention, is erroneous.  
>
Government’s response:  
[120] Government argues the judge was correct in concluding the Arbitration  
Board was without jurisdiction to determine the constitutional validity of s.  
9 of the restraint legislation. Its counsel acknowledges that the question of  
the Board’s jurisdiction over the dispute’s subject matter hinges, as Weber  
enunciates, on whether the “essential character” of the dispute arises from  
the collective agreement. In the situation at bar, however, Government’s  
counsel maintains that on proper application of legal principle, the judge’s  
Page: 39  
conclusion that the dispute in “its essential character” does not arise from  
the collective agreement is unassailable.  
[121] Counsel for Government contends a crucial distinction exists between a  
dispute that arises from a collective agreement “and a legislative imperative  
that overrides a provision in the collective agreement”. Moreover, he  
argues that in the case at bar the arbitration panel was asked “to decide the  
threshold question of what constituted the collective agreement”. Such a  
question, he adds, could not be one “arising from” the collective agreement.  
The basic thrust of Government’s submission, however, is that it is the  
court, not an arbitration panel, which had the competence “to determine the  
constitutional validity of legislation that interfered with the pay equity  
adjustments” payable under the collective agreement.  
[122] In support of its submission, Government’s counsel cites authority holding  
that, although arbitration tribunals are endowed “with jurisdiction to  
consider questions of law, including constitutional questions”, they have no  
power “to decide the constitutional validity” of their enabling legislation.  
From this linchpin, counsel argues, whilst the arbitration panel at bar had  
“jurisdiction to consider questions of fact and law in interpreting, applying  
and administering the collective agreement”, it was devoid of power to pass  
upon the constitutional validity or on the construction of, the “legislatively  
imposed provision in the Act”, which “limits the jurisdiction of the panel”.  
[123] In addition to the firm legal foundation upon which Government contends  
the appealed jurisdictional ruling rests, its counsel submits the judge was  
correct in treating pragmatic considerations as also prescribing jurisdictional  
limits of arbitration panels. Citing authority to illustrate the legitimacy of  
such considerations, he underscores the ad hoc nature of the composition of  
such panels. While such composition, Government’s argument reasons, “is  
well suited to the determination of disputes regarding the interpretation,  
application or administration of the terms of a collective agreement”, the  
judge was correct in concluding “a panel of this composition is not suited to  
the task of determining a question such as the constitutional validity of the  
Act, a statute having broad public policy implications far beyond the  
collective agreement at issue”.  
[124] In pressing this unsuitability to pass upon the public policy implications  
engaged in legislative constitutional assessments, Government takes the  
stance that “the same level of credibility and breath of experience in the  
development of policy and law” used to justify clothing arbitration boards  
Page: 40  
with exclusive jurisdiction over matters arising under collective agreements,  
“would not apply to an ad hoc arbitration panel appointed by the parties”.  
In particular, this argument stresses, an arbitration panel’s expertise “does  
not extend to the kind of question posed by the constitutional challenge” to  
the restraint legislation. This is because, it goes on to explain, “(t)he ad hoc  
panel must focus on the particular collective agreement at issue without  
consideration for relevant broad, but important, policy considerations”.  
Counsel draws this phase of Government’s rejoinder to NAPE’s appeal to  
its close by stating the judge was correct in holding the “policy concerns”  
are “well outside” the kinds of subject matter “intended to be addressed by  
such a panel”.  
[125] As will be observed from the foregoing summary of the response to NAPE’s  
challenge to the judge’s jurisdiction ruling, Government’s position is that  
the holding of the Arbitration Board’s lack of jurisdiction over the subject  
matter of the pay equity dispute at bar rests on sound and sustainable legal  
and pragmatic foundations.  
>
analysis of submissions:  
[126] As an overview of the foregoing summaries of the submissions of counsel  
show, the merits of the judge’s holding that the Arbitration Board lacked  
jurisdiction over the subject matter of this dispute turn, in part, on which of  
the two parties’ positions should be given sway. This inquiry firstly  
requires analysis of whether NAPE’s complaint over the reneging on the  
promise to pay the retroactive wage equity adjustments arises out of the  
collective agreement. If it does, as NAPE contends, then the judge’s  
determination that the Board lacked jurisdiction over the dispute’s subject  
matter must be held incorrect, and inquiry will have to be had into whether  
that tribunal also had jurisdiction over the remedy sought. If it does not,  
and Government’s contention that the subject matter of the dispute arises  
out of the restraint legislation and its constitutional validity is correct, then  
the judge’s determination, and his holding that the Board was without  
jurisdiction over the dispute raised through the Union’s grievance, will have  
to be upheld without the necessity of further inquiry.  
[127] With due respect to the judge’s opinion that the Arbitration Board lacked  
jurisdiction over the subject matter of the grievance at bar, and to counsel  
for Government who would have this Court endorse that finding, agreement  
cannot be voiced with it. This is essentially because the “core dispute” was  
Page: 41  
not, as preceding para. 69 notes the judge defined it, the constitutional  
validity of s. 9 of the restraint legislation. The dispute between the parties  
to this appeal was, as preceding para. 117 records NAPE’s counsel contends  
it to be, Government’s failure to make the retroactive pay equity  
adjustments that it had undertaken to pay in the addenda to the collective  
agreements. As NAPE’s counsel points out, the dispute taken through the  
grievances was for money due under “the Pay equity provisions of all  
Collective Agreements”. NAPE’s complaint was over Government’s  
reneging on its promise arising out of its undertakings under the collective  
agreements to pay the retroactive pay equity adjustments. Thus, to borrow  
from McLachlin J.’s terminology in the passages from Weber quoted in  
preceding paras. 114 and 115, the “essential character” of the dispute  
“regardless of how it may be characterized legally” is one arising under the  
collective agreement at bar, thereby grounding jurisdiction over the subject  
matter in the Arbitration Board.  
[128] The underlying flaw in Government’s jurisdictional submission lies in its  
classifying the essential character of the dispute as “the constitutional  
validity of legislation that interfered with the pay equity adjustments”  
payable to affected employees under the collective agreement. It is certainly  
true that the dispute engages the issue of the constitutional validity of the  
restraint legislation. Indeed, the dispute arguably might be, to borrow once  
more from Weber, “characterized legally” as such, just as it may be also  
classified as one centered on Government’s repudiation of its obligation to  
compensate for retroactive pay equity adjustments, which is the issue raised  
in the grievances that led to the arbitration proceedings. How one  
characterizes the dispute will likely depend upon from whose side it is being  
viewed.  
[129] In the final analysis, however, it is really of no import to the ultimate  
resolution of the Arbitration Board’s jurisdiction how the dispute raised by  
the grievances is characterized legally. As Weber holds in the excerpt from  
it reproduced in para. 114, the issue of arbitral jurisdiction is not determined  
by “whether the action defined legally, is independent of the collective  
agreement”, but “by whether the dispute is one ‘arising under [the]  
collective agreement’”. The constitutional validity of the restraint  
legislation does not arise out of the collective agreement, as does the  
disputed right to compensation.  
Page: 42  
[130] It is important to keep in mind that the constitutional issue surfaces in this  
matter as a result of Government’s defence that its indebtedness, which had  
arisen under the collective agreements affected by this proceeding, was  
extinguished by legislation outside of those agreements. In effect,  
Government is seizing legislation independent of those agreements as a  
shield, and is raising it in an attempt to gain immunity from its obligation to  
pay the disputed compensation under the collective agreements. The  
constitutionality question came as a result of NAPE’s rejoinder, and is  
aimed at stripping Government of that shield. The constitutional validity  
issue, then, is directed towards establishing that legislation extraneous to the  
collective agreements is of no force and effect insofar as their commitments  
to implement the pay equity adjustments is concerned. It did not arise from  
those agreements, but was brought forth for consideration in response to the  
defence in the dispute over liability for the retroactive compensation that  
arose out of a collective agreement. The resolution of that response was  
consequently within the jurisdictional purview of the Board.  
[131] Actually, the significance which Government’s argument attributes to the  
distinction between a dispute that arises from a collective agreement and “a  
legislative imperative that overrides a provision in the collective agreement”  
is revelatory of the underlying flaw in its reasoning advanced in support of  
the judge’s finding of lack of arbitral jurisdiction over the subject matter of  
the dispute. There is no doubt that the superior force of the supervening  
overriding effect of the restraint enactment’s “legislative imperative”, upon  
which preceding para. 121 records Government counsel to be insisting,  
could not be logically classified as “arising from” the collective agreement.  
It does not follow, however, that the need to address the effect of that  
subsequent legislative development, which that question requires,  
transposes the essential character of the dispute to one “arising outside” of  
the collective agreement, thereby divesting the Board of jurisdiction over  
the dispute’s subject matter. The essential nature of the dispute clearly  
remains NAPE’s complaint over Government’s reneging on its promise  
under the collective agreement to pay the retroactive pay equity adjustment.  
The restraint legislation gave rise to a legitimate issue regarding  
Government’s obligation to honour that promise. However, NAPE’s attack  
on the constitutionality of the legislation does not change the nature of the  
dispute as one arising from an undertaking under the collective agreement.  
Page: 43  
>
governing authority:  
[132] Moreover, it is incorrect to portray arbitration tribunals as having no power  
to entertain questions requiring them “to determine the constitutional  
validity of legislation” that purports to interfere with undertakings made  
under collective agreements. The law is settled in that regard. In the extract  
from his judgment quoted in preceding para. 109, La Forest J. in Chuddy  
Chicks expressly indicates that arbitral jurisdiction extends to competence  
to pass on the Charter’s impact on “the whole of the matter before” a  
tribunal. Earlier, in the same vein, but in even more explicit terms, La  
Forest J., in Douglas/Kwantlen Faculty Assn. v. Douglas College, [1990]  
3 S.C.R. 570, had written thusly at p. 594:  
C
Section 52(1) of the Constitution Act, 1982 provides that any law that  
is inconsistent with the provisions of the Constitution of Canada - the  
supreme law of the land - is, to the extent of its inconsistency, of no  
force and effect. A tribunal must respect the Constitution so that if it  
finds invalid a law it is called upon to apply, it is bound to treat it as  
having no force or effect.  
[133] Likewise, having earlier in para. 56 quoted Lord Denning as having  
observed there is “not one law for arbitrators and another for the court”,  
McLachlin J., following the Supreme Court’s kindred holding in Douglas  
College, went on to conclude in para. 61 of Weber:  
C
... a labour arbitrator can consider the Charter, find laws inoperative  
for conflict with it, and go on to grant remedies in the exercise of his  
powers under the Labour Code .... If an arbitrator can find a law  
violative of the Charter, it would seem he or she can determine  
whether conduct in the administration of the collective agreement  
violates the Charter and likewise grant remedies.  
[134] Ample and clear authority exists, therefore, supporting arbitral jurisdiction  
to determine the constitutional validity of legislation in addressing dispute  
arising from collective agreements. Counsel for Government is not  
challenging that proposition. Instead, he distinguishes this case from the  
precedents supporting the proposition, whilst aligning the circumstances of  
this case with other authorities.  
Page: 44  
>
Government’s view of authorities:  
[135] Government’s counsel opened his treatment of the authorities by pointing  
out that Weber involved inquiry into whether conduct in the administration  
of a collective agreement violated the Charter, whilst Douglas College  
focused upon whether a provision in a collective agreement providing for  
mandatory retirement out of which the dispute’s subject matter arose, on a  
proper interpretation of it, was inconsistent with the Charter’s s. 15  
equality rights thereby requiring it to be treated as having no force and  
effect. Accordingly, with these two cases falling within the general rubric  
of disputes which, in their essential character, arose from the administration  
or interpretation of collective agreements, counsel acknowledges the  
correctness of having held them to have come within the ambit of exclusive  
arbitral jurisdiction.  
[136] As preceding para. 122 has already pointed out, while counsel for  
Government also acknowledges the arbitration panel at bar had “jurisdiction  
to consider questions of law and fact in interpreting, applying and  
administering the collective agreement”, he maintains it was not empowered  
to pass on the constitutional validity, or on the construction, of the  
“legislatively imposed provision in the Act” limiting “the jurisdiction of the  
panel”. In other words, counsel is contending the Arbitration Board lacked  
jurisdiction to determine the force and effect of the restraints imposed on  
Government’s undertakings to implement pay equity under the collective  
agreements. He enlists Cooper v. Canada (Human Rights Commission),  
[1996] 3 S.C.R. 854 to support this assertion.  
[137] Cooper involved complaints of airline pilots who were being retired at age  
sixty pursuant to a provision in their collective agreement. Alleging that  
this was discriminatory in light of the general Canadian practice of requiring  
retirement of most employees at age sixty-five, the pilots disputed the  
provision in complaints filed with the Canadian Human Rights Commission.  
Section 15(c) of the Canadian Human Rights Act, R.S.C. 1985, c.H-6  
explicitly provided it was not discriminatory practice for an individual to be  
terminated from employment because that individual had reached the  
normal age of retirement for employees in similar positions. The underlying  
question, as articulated by La Forest J. in his lead majority decision in  
Cooper, boiled down to whether the Commission could ignore s. 15(c) of  
its Act, which constituted its enabling legislation, by entertaining  
complaints over the allegedly discriminatory earlier retirements than the  
Page: 45  
general Canadian practice. All of the complaints in Cooper effectively  
rested on the ground that the compulsory terminations at sixty must be  
struck as contrary to the Charter. To have allowed these complaints to  
proceed by constituting a panel to hear them was, in fact, deemed to be  
tantamount to striking down s. 15(3) by invoking the Charter, and the  
Commission refused to do so. It was that decision which was before the  
Supreme Court of Canada.  
[138] The precise legal issue arising out of the foregoing circumstances in Cooper  
was defined by La Forest J. in para. 30 of his judgment thusly:  
C
... whether the Canadian Human Rights Commission or a tribunal  
appointed by it to investigate a complaint has power to determine the  
constitutionality of a provision of their enabling statute, ...  
The issue was answered in the negative at the conclusion of the majority judgment  
where La Forest J. held in para. 66:  
C
... while a tribunal may have jurisdiction to consider legal and  
constitutional questions, logic demands that it has no ability to  
question the constitutional validity of a limiting provision of the Act.  
[139] Counsel for Government equates Cooper’s negative resolution of the  
foregoing stated legal issue to the situation at bar. Thus, just as the Human  
Rights Commission was correct in refusing to entertain a complaint of  
discrimination based on general retirement criteria when its enabling statute  
limited such inquiries to normative practices prevailing in retirements of  
employees in similar positions, counsel reasons the arbitration panel at bar  
was precluded from ignoring the subsequent legislatively imposed  
limitation on implementations of pay equity adjustments that foreclosed  
retroactive payments otherwise payable under the affected employees’  
collective agreement. In the view of counsel for Government, just as La  
Forest J. reasoned in Cooper that consideration by the Commission of the  
pilots’ complaint would have been tantamount to striking down the  
normative provision of its enabling legislation for want of Charter  
compliance, the decision here under appeal was correct in treating the  
Board’s acceptance of NAPE’s complaint over the disputed retroactive pay  
equity adjustments as effectively constituting a ruling of constitutional  
invalidity, for want of compliance with the Charter’s equality rights, of the  
legislatively imposed limiting provision in the restraint legislation  
foreclosing implementation retroactively of pay equity adjustments.  
Page: 46  
[140] With respect, apart altogether from the fact that the restraint legislation did  
not constitute the Board’s enabling statute, this analogy drawn by  
Government’s counsel is inapt. Cooper speaks to the reality that the  
Canadian Human Rights Commission is a statutory body whose powers are  
limited to the precincts laid down in its constituting legislation, excursions  
from which are subject to being checked by courts on the standard of  
correctness. Labour arbitration boards, on the other hand, are ad hoc  
bodies, created when parties commit their disputes under collective  
agreements to the arbitration process and which, as preceding para. 113  
notes St. Anne Nackawic to affirm, are endowed with exclusive jurisdiction  
“to consider claims arising out of rights created by a collective agreement”,  
alleged excursions from which are subject to judicial review, not on  
correctness, but on the standard of patently unreasonable error.  
[141] The powers of labour arbitration boards, therefore, are wide ranging in that  
they stem immediately from exclusive jurisdictional authority to pass on all  
disputes arising out of collective agreements. Their authority in this regard  
is complete, and includes the power to address Charter issues in relation to  
disputes whose essential character arises, in the words of Weber “from the  
interpretation, application, administration or violation of the collective  
agreement” (see preceding para. 115). Conversely, the jurisdiction of the  
Canadian Human Rights Commission under scrutiny in Cooper is confined  
to that directly conferred upon it by its enabling legislation. Such statutory  
bodies must remain within the bounds of their creation. They have no  
latitude to engage, as it were, in frolics of their own by deciding, or acting  
as if, limitations on the powers conferred on them under their enabling  
statutes do not stand up to constitutional muster. Boards such as the one at  
bar, however, as Chuddy Chicks, Douglas College and Weber affirm,  
have jurisdiction to address the constitutional validity of legislation insofar  
as that concern impacts upon a dispute whose essential character arises out  
of collective agreements.  
[142] It is, then, this distinction between labour arbitration boards and statutory  
bodies which forecloses the analogy drawn between Cooper and the  
circumstances at bar. Equation of the circumstances at bar to Cooper does  
not assist counsel’s jurisdictional submissions. Actually, the underlying  
flaw in Government’s submissions, already mentioned in preceding para.  
128, can be seen to surface in this misplaced attempt to equate Cooper to  
this case. Although Government may well legally characterize this dispute  
Page: 47  
as one engaging the issue of constitutional validity of a legislative provision  
under the Charter, this is not material here as it was in Cooper. Once  
more, it needs to be reiterated that the jurisdictional issue in this appeal is,  
as Weber underscores, “whether the dispute is one ‘arising under [the]  
collective agreement”, and “not whether the action, defined legally, is  
independent of the collective agreement”. Counsel’s analogy misses that  
distinction.  
[143] The second authority enlisted by counsel for Government in support of his  
thesis that jurisdiction over the dispute at bar lay with the court, and not the  
Arbitration Board, is Service Employees International Union, Local 204  
v. Ontario (Attorney-General) (1997), 35 O.R. (3d) 508. In this case  
Local 204 applied to the General Division of the Ontario Court for a  
declaration that an amendment to pay equity legislation violated s. 15, as  
well as s. 28 of the Charter. The effect of the amendment was to  
substantially eliminate pay equity adjustments for women in the Ontario  
Public Service, and the broader public sector, who had been scheduled to  
receive them by virtue of undertakings in the parent legislation. O’Leary J.  
granted the Union’s application and declared the amendment of no force  
and effect.  
[144] There is no need to delve in any depth into the detailed facts of Service  
Employees International. That case is being advanced by counsel for  
Government as one in which the court, not an arbitration panel, was  
recognized as invested with jurisdiction to determine the constitutional  
validity of legislation that interfered with pay equity adjustments. Counsel  
avails of this recognition to buttress his submission, recounted in preceding  
para. 122, that the panel at bar was devoid of power to pass on the  
constitutional validity, or construction, of the “legislatively imposed  
provision in the Act”, i.e. s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act, which  
“limits the jurisdiction of the panel”.  
[145] The attempted analogy of the case at bar with Service Employees  
International, however, no more assists Government’s jurisdictional  
argument than does its equation to Cooper. This is because the dispute in  
Service Employees International did not arise out of a collective  
agreement from which evolved a collateral issue of constitutionality, as is  
the situation in the circumstances at bar. The focus was not upon any  
collective agreement in Service Employees International, but directly  
engaged a question of a legislative amendment’s compatibility with  
Page: 48  
constitutional protections guaranteed under the Charter. It is true that both  
that case and the one at bar complain of reneging by Governments on their  
undertakings to implement pay equity adjustments for female employees in  
the public service, and of reliance by Governments on supervening  
overriding legislation to justify their actions. However, the dispute over  
governmental obligation to pay them did not arise out of undertakings in  
collective agreements in Service Employees International, as it did in the  
case at bar. The dispute there rather arose out of the enforceability of the  
obligation as given in the pay equity legislation enacted prior to its  
amendment. Hence, there was no dispute arising out of a collective  
agreement to commit to arbitration. The court was the only forum in which  
to air the dispute.  
[146] Once more, strains of the underlying flaw permeating Government’s  
jurisdictional argument can be discerned in this second misplaced analogy.  
The fact that the court in Service Employees International had jurisdiction  
over the dispute had nothing to do with the turning issue’s capacity to be  
legally characterized as engaging constitutional validity under the Charter  
of the legislative provision affecting Government’s obligation to make the  
pay equity adjustments as promised. It had the decision-making authority  
because the disputed obligation arose under the initial legislation and not  
under any collective agreement on which arbitral jurisdiction might be  
founded. Here, once more, counsel for Government misses that essential  
distinction.  
[147] Because the circumstances in Cooper and Service Employees  
International are distinguishable from the situation at bar, these authorities  
do not impair the conclusion, drawable from the preceding analysis of the  
respective submissions of counsel, that Government’s arguments, in support  
of the judge’s holding that the Arbitration Board lacked jurisdiction over the  
subject matter of this dispute, do not rest on a firm and sustainable legal  
foundation. Unless the second arm of Government’s response to NAPE’s  
position, which advances pragmatic considerations as a basis for lack of  
arbitral jurisdiction over the subject matter, must be given sway, the Union’s  
contention that the subject matter of this dispute lay within the exclusive  
purview of the Board’s jurisdictional reach must prevail. Attention will  
now focus on this final aspect of Government’s response.  
>
Government’s pragmatic position:  
Page: 49  
[148] The short answer to counsel’s response that the ad hoc nature of the  
composition of arbitration panels renders them unsuited, from a pragmatic  
standpoint, to the task of resolving questions of constitutional validity of  
legislation affecting disputes arising from collective agreements is that  
pragmatic concerns are not to be taken into account by courts as  
determinative factors in addressing arbitral jurisdiction. Authoritative  
statement to that effect is contained in para. 59 of La Forest J.’s judgment in  
Cooper where he asserts “practical considerations cannot dictate the  
outcome of the issue presently before this Court”. As already pointed out,  
the “issue” in Cooper involved the jurisdictional parameters of decision-  
making powers of the Canadian Human Rights Commission. Although this  
matter involves an ad hoc labour arbitration board adopted by the parties to  
arbitrate their differences, as opposed to a body directly created by statute,  
the irrelevancy of “practical considerations” as a decisive factor is equally  
applicable to labour arbitral dispositions. Whether jurisdiction stems from a  
dispute whose essential character arises from a collective agreement, or  
directly from a tribunal’s enabling statute, there is no distinction insofar as  
concerns the irrelevancy of “practical considerations” bearing on the  
suitability of the body to exercise its jurisdictional powers.  
[149] That irrelevancy stems from the reality that it matters not a whit how a court  
may view the suitability of labour arbitration panels to resolve the  
constitutional validity of legislation affecting disputes before them. Such a  
consideration clearly falls within the ambit of the legislative power under  
the Separation of Powers Doctrine which Lamer C.J.C. in para. 10 of his  
concurring judgment in Cooper describes as “(o)ne of the defining features  
of the Canadian Constitution”. The suitability of arbitration boards to  
exercise their powers is a policy decision falling squarely within the  
legislative domain under that Doctrine, and the consequential legislation is  
the enunciation of the policy of that branch of government. While it lies  
with the judiciary to interpret the scope of the enunciated policy as  
expressed in a statute, pragmatic consideration of the policy which  
prompted the legislation does not rest with the courts. That pragmatic  
concern is strictly a matter of policy within the purview of the Legislature.  
This is not to say, however, that questions of practicality are totally  
immaterial to statutory construction. Thus, as La Forest J. went on to state  
in para. 59 of his majority judgment in Cooper, “... practical considerations  
Page: 50  
may be of assistance in determining the intention of Parliament, but they are  
not determinative”.  
[150] In the result, counsel’s resort to pragmatic considerations does not assist his  
argument in support of the judge’s holding that the Arbitration Board “did  
not have jurisdiction to determine the constitutional validity of the Act”  
which he construed the dispute to be “over”. It was on this erroneous  
finding that the judge based his conclusion that the Board lacked  
jurisdiction over the subject matter of the dispute at bar, and that its decision  
could be set aside on that account alone.  
[151] The flaw in this pragmatic arm of counsel’s response to his counterpart’s  
attack on the judge’s jurisdictional disposition can be seen in his concluding  
comments with respect to it where, as preceding para. 124 records, he  
argues the judge was correct in holding the “policy concerns” are “well  
outside” the kinds of subject matter “intended to be addressed by such a  
panel”. In fact, the suitability of labour arbitration tribunals to deal with the  
constitutional validity of legislation affecting disputes arising from  
collective agreements is a “policy concern” which is “well outside” the  
judiciary’s jurisdiction, and rests squarely within the competence of the  
Legislature under the now constitutionally entrenched Doctrine of the  
Separation of Powers.  
[152] Accordingly, counsel’s pragmatic position does not assist his argument that  
the finding of the lack of arbitral jurisdiction over the subject matter should  
be upheld.  
>
subject matter ruling:  
[153] For reasons expressed in the foregoing analysis of both counsel’s  
submissions, and of the authorities advanced to support their respective  
positions, it will be apparent that the dispute addressed by the Arbitration  
Board arose out of the collective agreements. This being the case, as NAPE  
contends, the judge’s determination that the Board lacked jurisdiction over  
the dispute’s subject matter, i.e., Government’s entitlement to renege on its  
promise to pay the retroactive pay equity adjustment that it had undertaken  
to make in the collective agreements, was incorrect. By the same token,  
Government’s contention that the dispute’s subject matter arose out of the  
restraint legislation, and its constitutional validity, is incorrect. That  
legislation and its enforceability were issues in a dispute whose essential  
character arose “from the interpretation, application, administration or  
Page: 51  
violation” of the collective agreements. Accordingly, under authority of  
Weber and the other authorities in similar vein mentioned in the foregoing  
discussions, the Board constituted to arbitrate the dispute at bar had  
jurisdiction over its subject matter.  
[154] It follows that the judge erred in holding the “dispute did not arise either  
expressly or inferentially from the Collective Agreement”, and in portraying  
it as being “over the constitutional validity of Section 9 of the Act”. It is  
acknowledged the constitutional validity of the Act was an issue in the  
dispute. The judge erred, however, in holding the Board had no jurisdiction  
to consider that issue, and in consequently holding the panel lacked  
jurisdiction over the subject matter of the disputed claim to the retroactive  
pay equity adjustments under the collective agreements.  
÷
the remedy:  
first inquiry:  
>
[155] Having found the Arbitration Board lacked jurisdiction over the subject  
matter, there was no need for the judge to have continued inquiry into its  
decision-making power over the remedy. Thus, in light of holding that this  
second of the three essential bases of arbitral jurisdiction enunciated in  
Chuddy Chicks was absent, there was no necessity to explore the presence  
of the third, and the judge proceeded to his conclusion that Board  
jurisdiction was lacking over the representative grievance at bar. In view of  
the foregoing contrary determination that the Board had jurisdiction over  
the subject matter, it is now necessary to this appeal’s disposition of the  
jurisdictional issue to address the Board’s competence over the remedy.  
>
NAPE’s position:  
[156] In advancing her argument that arbitral jurisdiction also exists over the  
remedy, NAPE’s counsel places heavy reliance on three of the cases already  
encountered in the preceding discussion exploring the Board’s decision-  
making power over the subject matter, namely: Chuddy Chicks, Douglas  
College and Weber, whilst placing particular reliance upon the latter  
authority.  
[157] Counsel opens her argument by maintaining the Board’s jurisdictional  
power over the remedy flows from s. 52(1) of the Constitution Act, 1982,  
which renders any law inconsistent with the Charter of “no force or effect”  
Page: 52  
to the “extent of the inconsistency”. She argues the power to engage s.  
52(1) as a remedy arises when, as Lamer C.J.C. concluded in Schachter v.  
Canada, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 679 at 717, “a law is itself held to be  
unconstitutional, as opposed to simply a particular action taken under it”.  
The gist of NAPE’s submission on the Board’s remedial jurisdiction,  
therefore, is that, with arbitration boards being competent to determine the  
constitutional validity of legislation affecting disputes arising from  
collective agreements, it logically follows that a finding of  
unconstitutionality engages s. 52(1); and, that a board making such a  
finding would be empowered to rule the legislation of “no force and effect”,  
insofar as its constitutional inconsistency affected the dispute before it,  
thereby exercising jurisdiction over that remedy.  
[158] In support of such remedial jurisdiction, NAPE’s counsel points out that in  
the earliest days following the Charter’s entrenchment into Canadian law,  
the Supreme Court of Canada held s. 52(1)’s power to refuse to apply  
unconstitutional law was not the exclusive purview of superior courts. In  
this regard, she directs attention to the ruling in R. v. Big M Drug Mart  
Ltd., [1985] 1 S.C.R. 295 that provincial, as well as superior courts, have  
authority to invoke s. 52(1) and refuse to apply unconstitutional legislation.  
As already noted, counsel submits Chuddy Chicks, Douglas College and  
Weber as authorities supporting her position that arbitration boards are  
similarly endowed with authority to declare unconstitutional law, purporting  
to affect disputes arising from collective agreements, of no force and effect  
under s. 52(1) of the Constitution Act. To avoid unnecessary repetition of  
them, the thrust of her argument based on these three authorities will be left  
to the ensuing analysis of counsel’s respective submissions on this remedial  
jurisdictional question.  
>
Government’s response:  
[159] Government’s response to NAPE’s position opens by attacking the  
Arbitration Board’s unanimous finding of its jurisdiction over the remedy.  
The Board chairperson’s decision had reasoned, inasmuch as s. 39(1) of the  
Public Service Collective Bargaining Act, R.S.N., 1990, c.P-42, operated  
to effectively insert in the collective agreement a phrase providing for  
binding arbitration, it follows that arbitrators acting under that enactment  
were empowered to determine remedies appropriate to disposition of  
disputes. Counsel for Government effectively argues, however, that this  
Page: 53  
reasoning is too simplistic, maintaining that a collective agreement’s  
incorporation of “a provision for arbitration to settle disputes arising from  
the agreement cannot, by itself, clothe the arbitration panel with unlimited  
remedial power”.  
[160] Instead, Government’s counsel insists, the proper focus is not s. 39(1), but s.  
40(4) of the Public Service Collective Bargaining Act which provides:  
C
An arbitration board shall not make an award which would amend or  
change a Collective Agreement, a judgment or an earlier award.  
Portraying the effect of the restraint legislation as altering the terms of the  
collective agreement presently under appellate scrutiny “by rendering void any  
provision authorizing retroactive payment of pay equity adjustments, and instead,  
stipulating that the wage adjustments would commence on the date they were  
agreed upon”, counsel argues it was the collective agreement “as amended by the  
Act, over which the arbitration panel had jurisdiction”. From this standpoint,  
knitting into the fabric of his argument s. 40(4) of the Public Service Collective  
Bargaining Act, counsel concludes “(to) allow the panel to determine that the  
legislatively imposed provision is inoperative would constitute an amendment to  
the Collective Agreement” which, in his opinion, would be “a remedy that is  
clearly beyond the jurisdiction of the panel”.  
[161] By dint of the foregoing reasoning, therefore, counsel for Government takes  
the position that a finding that s. 9 of the restraint legislation “is  
unconstitutional would alter the collective agreement by changing the date  
on which wage adjustments payments would commence”. Accordingly, he  
submits the Arbitration Board lacked jurisdiction to grant the remedy, under  
s. 52(1) of the Constitution Act, “upon finding the legislation to be a  
violation of the Charter”.  
>
analysis of submissions:  
[162] The three authorities upon which NAPE’s counsel places heavy reliance  
provide strong support for her position that the Arbitration Board had  
jurisdiction to invoke the remedy available under s. 52(1) of the  
Constitution Act; and, to find s. 9 of the restraint legislation of no force  
and effect insofar as its inconsistency with Government’s obligation to  
make the retroactive pay equity adjustments under the collective agreement  
was concerned. That remedy was triggered, in her submission, when the  
Page: 54  
Board made its ruling on the constitutional invalidity of s. 9 upon that  
obligation, which ruling was within the purview of the Board’s powers.  
[163] Chuddy Chicks supports NAPE’s position in the distinction which that  
authority draws between the making for formal declarations of invalidity,  
and treating an impugned legislative provision as invalid for the purpose of  
the matter in dispute which is the situation at bar. NAPE’s counsel puts  
forth the following passage from p. 17 of La Forest J.’s judgment in  
Chuddy Chicks which draws that distinction:  
C
... a formal declaration of invalidity is not a remedy which is available  
to the Board. Instead, the Board merely treats any impugned  
provision as invalid for the purposes of the matter before it. Given  
that this is not tantamount to a formal declaration of invalidity, a  
remedy exercisable only by the superior courts, the ruling of the  
Board on a Charter issue does not constitute a binding legal  
precedent, but is limited in its applicability to the matter in which it  
arises.  
[164] NAPE’s position is further fortified by another passage from La Forest J.’s  
judgment in Douglas College which has been earlier reproduced in para.  
132. As will be noted that extract asserts that the arbitration process  
established under the collective agreement not only had the power to apply  
s. 52(1) of the Constitution Act, but was “bound” to “respect the  
Constitution” by treating “a law it is called on to apply” and that “it finds  
invalid ... as having no force and effect”. Hence, with the power to  
consider the constitutionality of the restraint legislation upon the disputed  
retroactive pay equity adjustments, the Board was actually obliged to  
declare the legislation of no force and effect upon Government’s  
undertakings to pay them under the collective agreement if it found the  
subsequent legislative measure unconstitutional.  
[165] Clinching authority, if needed, is furnished in the extract from McLachlin  
J.’s judgment in Weber which is reproduced in preceding para. 133. As  
reference to it will show, it clearly states that arbitral jurisdiction exists to  
“grant remedies” if a law is found “violative of the Charter” in the course of  
addressing “whether conduct in the administration of the collective  
agreement violates the Charter”.  
[166] These three authorities, therefore, lend unequivocal support to NAPE’s  
position that the Arbitration Board had jurisdiction over the remedy in this  
dispute. With respect, Government counsel’s position, which in the final  
Page: 55  
analysis rests on s. 40(4) of the Public Service Collective Bargaining Act,  
does not impair the validity of his counterpart’s position.  
[167] Government’s counsel is attempting here to deflect the significance, which  
preceding para. 159 has noted the Arbitration Board placed on s. 39(1) of  
the Public Service Collective Bargaining Act, onto s. 40(4) of that  
enactment. The thrust of his position is that, in enacting s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation, Government made it a part of the collective agreements and, the  
Arbitration Board, being precluded by s. 40(4) of the collective bargaining  
legislation from amending or changing a collective agreement, would be  
doing precisely that in determining the legislatively imposed restraint term  
was of no force and effect. Thus, counsel essentially posits the Board was  
bereft of jurisdiction to rule s. 9 of the restraint legislation invalid because  
such a ruling would be ultra vires the Board’s arbitral powers, being in  
violation of s. 40(4) of the collective bargaining legislation.  
[168] The first, and perhaps most obvious, rejoinder to Government’s foregoing  
position is that the same s. 52(1) of the Constitution Act here under  
discussion makes any law inconsistent with the Charter of no force and  
effect, and this decree would supercede s. 9 of the restraint legislation if that  
statutory provision is constitutionally invalidated. Apart from the question  
of its potential constitutional incompatibility, however, Government’s  
position is also intrinsically flawed in that it presupposes an agreement  
between two parties may be unilaterally amended by one of them without  
the consent of the other. Such a premise is axiomatically untenable, being  
diametrically at odds with the very conceptual notion of agreement. That  
premise may not be made tenable by invoking parliamentary supremacy,  
and lifting one single provision from the context of the Public Service  
Collective Bargaining Act to counter the underlying purpose of that statute  
of which the provision forms a part. Yet, with respect, this is what  
Government’s s. 40(4) argument does.  
[169] The policy of the Public Service Collective Bargaining Act on its initial  
passage in 1973 was to extend collective bargaining rights for the first time  
to employees in the public sector. The legislation’s continued existence  
stands witness to the reality that this policy has remained intact since then.  
Concomitant with that policy must logically be implicit understanding that,  
normally, Government will respect, and hold itself bound to, employer  
obligations undertaken in agreements reached through the collective  
bargaining process. This is not to suggest that Government should be taken  
Page: 56  
to have exempted public sector collective agreements from subsequent  
enactments of general application which may affect undertakings given in  
those agreements. Neither is the suggestion to be inferred that Government,  
in extending collective bargaining rights to the public sector, has necessarily  
rendered itself powerless to affect rights and benefits conferred in  
agreements or legislation by specific legislative intervention.  
[170] Legislative power to enact constitutionally compatible legislation affecting  
benefits previously gained through the public sector collective bargaining  
process is not questioned in dismissing counsel’s s. 40(4) argument. Its  
rejection is rather because s. 40(2) does not admit to construction that  
permits it to be used to support lack of arbitral jurisdiction over the  
grievance at bar. The purpose of s. 40(2) of the Public Service Collective  
Bargaining Act is to speak to the breadth of arbitral power that is preserved  
through the curial deference standard. It tells arbitrators addressing disputes  
whose essential character arises out of public sector collective agreements  
that, as wide as their jurisdictional scope may be, it does not extend to  
amending or changing the terms of those agreements. In effect, therefore, s.  
40(4) is directed towards assuring the integrity of the compact. It does not  
buttress argument foreclosing arbitral jurisdiction over the constitutionality  
and construction of legislation affecting subsisting collective agreements to  
which purpose counsel is seeking to enlist s. 40(4).  
[171] Moreover, it must be borne in mind that the purpose of the Act, of which s.  
40(2) forms a part, is to extend collective bargaining rights to employees in  
the public sector. Public sector collective bargaining presupposes  
Government will hold to its bargain like any other party. This supposition  
is subject to two provisos. Firstly, it is subject to laws of general  
application from which the opposite party cannot expect to be exempted any  
more than other citizens and institutions in society. Secondly, the bargain is  
also subject to specific legislation aimed at modifying, or even nullifying it  
in pursuance of directed governmental policy to that end. In both of these  
instances, as will presently be explained, Charter considerations may come  
into play. Absent valid constitutional challenge collective agreements in the  
public service domain are conditional on these two provisos. However, they  
must be laws of general application or specific legislation directed at the  
agreements that have been struck. One isolated collateral provision within  
an Act, such as s. 40(4), cannot be used to defeat the statutory purpose of  
the very legislative measure of which it is a part. This would constitute rank  
Page: 57  
perversion of statutory intent. As already noted, there is a rational  
explanation of s. 40(4)’s purpose which is consistent with the overall  
statutory objective of extending collective bargaining to persons employed  
in the public sector.  
[172] For the foregoing reasons, therefore, Government’s response in rebuttal of  
NAPE’s arguments supporting its position of lack of arbitral jurisdiction  
over the remedy is unsustainable.  
÷
jurisdictional disposition:  
[173] NAPE’s contention that the Arbitration Board had jurisdiction to hear  
the representative grievance over Government’s failure to have made the  
retroactive pay equity adjustments payable under the collective agreement is  
sustainable. It was common ground in all prior proceedings addressing the  
grievance that the Board had jurisdiction over the parties. On the footing of  
the foregoing reasoning, with due respect to the trial judge’s contrary  
opinion, the Board also had jurisdiction over the subject matter of the  
dispute initiated through the grievance. By the same token, the preceding  
reasoning explains why the Board must be held to have had jurisdiction  
over the remedy.  
[174] Accordingly, having had jurisdiction over “the parties, subject matter and  
remedy sought”, the Arbitration Board, under the law in that respect  
articulated in the excerpt from Chuddy Chicks reproduced in preceding  
para. 109, must be held to have had decision-making power over the  
substance of “the whole of the matter before it”. Included in that  
jurisdictional purview is the power to address the constitutional validity of  
s. 9 of the restraint legislation insofar as it affects the disputed obligation  
arising out of the collective agreement to make the pay equity adjustments.  
Indeed, it is accurate to underscore that the Board not only was empowered  
to address s. 9's constitutional validity, but was duty bound not to apply it if  
it found it to be inconsistent with the Charter.  
[175] As the foregoing account of the decision out of the Trial Division indicates,  
the opinion that the Board lacked jurisdiction over the dispute stemmed  
from the view that the board had no authority to determine the compliance  
of s. 9 of the restraint legislation with the Charter. Having made the  
holding that the Board did not lack jurisdiction to hear the grievances raised  
in the dispute before it, this judgment now turns to the constitutional  
Page: 58  
question, which is the second issue set out in the listing of them in  
preceding para. 108.  
The constitutional issue:  
÷
recapitulation:  
[176] At this juncture, it will be helpful to recapitulate the prior findings on the  
constitutionality issue. In the first place, it was the unanimous view that s. 9  
of the restraint legislation violated the equality rights entrenched in s. 15(1)  
of the Charter insofar as s. 9 impacted upon Government’s undertakings in  
the collective agreements to make the retroactive pay equity adjustments.  
All three members of the Board, as well as the judge, were in accord on that  
aspect of the issue.  
[177] The same unanimity was not shared over whether the violation was saved  
under s. 1 of the Charter, however. The Board, with Government’s  
nominee dissenting, found it was not saved. Accordingly s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act was held void and of no effect, under s. 52(1) of the  
Constitution Act, upon the terms of the Pay Equity Agreement, including  
the terms of Government’s obligations to make the retroactive pay equity  
adjustments incorporated in the collective agreements.  
[178] The judge subsequently overturned the Board’s finding on s. 1 of the  
Charter, reasoning that the Board had erred in finding the intervening  
restraint legislation’s infringement of the Charter’s s. 15(1) equality rights  
was not saved under s. 1 of the Charter. Hence, the judge reversed the  
Board’s decision of constitutional invalidity of s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation, and he ultimately went on to hold the provision foreclosed  
recovery of the pay equity adjustments claimed by NAPE.  
Page: 59  
÷
approach:  
[179] For the purpose of an orderly broaching of the constitutional issue in this  
appeal, it will be assumed, arguendo, that the language of s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation extinguishes Government’s undertakings in the Pay  
Equity Agreement, which had been incorporated into the collective  
agreements as undertakings to make the retroactive pay equity adjustments.  
If it is decided the judge’s conclusion that s. 9 meets constitutional muster  
should be upheld, then inquiry will ensue into whether that legislative  
provision admits to being statutorily construed to have such effect. In the  
meantime, it will be assumed s. 9's language did have that import.  
[180] Before exploring the sustainability of the judge’s review of the Board’s  
constitutional analysis, discussion will be undertaken of the appropriate  
standard of judicial review of public sector arbitral decisions on the  
constitutional validity of a legislative measure affecting a dispute under  
arbitration.  
÷
standard of judicial review:  
[181] The objective of this discussion is twofold. Firstly, in the course of  
broaching discussion of the standard of review of such arbitral  
constitutional decisions, it will at the same time define the standard for  
judicial review of statutory interpretations of arbitration tribunals. Then, it  
will proceed to determine whether the constitutional dispositions of the  
Board were reviewable by the judge on the stringent standard of correctness,  
or the more deferential one of patent unreasonableness. Inquiry into the  
merits of the judge’s holdings that the Board erred in law in finding the  
restraint legislation violated s. 15(1) of the Charter, and was not saved  
under s. 1 of the Charter, and into his statutory interpretation of the  
language of s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act, will commence with an  
overview of relevant authorities and applicable legislation providing  
direction on the proper standard of judicial review that had to be brought to  
bear in making such rulings.  
>
the C.U.P.E. case:  
[182] Four authorities out of the Supreme Court of Canada assist discussion of  
that inquiry. The first is C.U.P.E. v. N.B. Liquor Corporation, [1979] 2  
S.C.R. 227. In that case the Court addressed the power of a specialized  
tribunal to interpret legislation in acquitting its own statutory mandate to  
Page: 60  
administer “a comprehensive statute regulating labour relations” (see p. 235  
of C.U.P.E.) The legislation that the tribunal was called upon to construe  
prohibited filling positions of striking employees with any other employees.  
In so doing, New Brunswick’s Public Service Labour Relations Board had  
to interpret whether the replacement of strikers with management personnel  
contravened the legislative prohibition. Material to this discussion are the  
following words of Dickson J., who delivered the Court’s unanimous  
judgment, where he is recorded at p. 236 as stating that the Board in  
C.U.P.E. would not only:  
C
... not be required to be “correct” in its interpretation, but one would  
think that the Board was entitled to err and any such error would be  
protected from review by the privative clause ...  
Further along in C.U.P.E., Dickson J. indicated this entitlement to err in  
legislative construction extended up to the limit of patent unreasonableness. This  
being so, he defined when that boundary is reached, and the specialized tribunal’s  
legislative interpretation becomes reviewable, in terms of the following question  
that he formulated at p. 237:  
C
... was the Board’s interpretation so patently unreasonable that its  
construction cannot be rationally supported by the relevant legislation  
and demands intervention by the court upon review?  
>
the Syndicat case:  
[183] The Supreme Court of Canada expanded on C.U.P.E. in Syndicat des  
employés de production du Québec v. CLRB, [1984] 2 S.C.R. 412. As  
had C.U.P.E., this case also addressed the standard of judicial review of  
decisions made by specialized tribunals. There the tribunal was the  
Canadian Labour Relations Board. One of the issues addressed by the  
Court in Syndicat was the judicial review standard of legislative  
interpretations made by such boards within the limits of their jurisdictional  
powers. There the Board had interpreted a concerted refusal by unionized  
employees to work overtime as an unlawful strike within the meaning of s.  
180 of the Canada Labour Code. In contrast, the impugned interpretation  
at bar, which the foregoing reasoning has concluded was within its  
jurisdictional competence, is the Arbitration Board’s interpretation of s. 9 of  
the restraint legislation as extinguishing governmental obligations to make  
pay equity wage adjustments during the restraint period, and as being  
Page: 61  
constitutionally invalid by reason of its infringement of s. 15(1) of the  
Charter, and of this violation not being saved under the Charter’s s. 1.  
Especially germane to the instant discussion is the conclusion drawn by  
Beetz J., who authored the unanimous judgment in Syndicat, appearing on  
p. 443, that the “patently unreasonable interpretation rule” is the standard of  
judicial review over “a question considered as falling within” the  
jurisdictional limits of an administrative tribunal. Earlier, at p. 425, Beetz J.  
had concurred with the view that the question whether an illegal strike had  
occurred had been within the limits of the Canada Labour Relations Board’s  
jurisdictional reach.  
[184] Still earlier, at p. 420 of Syndicat, Beetz J. provided insight into why  
patently unreasonable errors of administrative tribunals are considered  
sufficiently serious to warrant interventions by courts upon judicial review.  
Thus, whilst referring to the passage from C.U.P.E. just reproduced in  
preceding para. 182, and styling patently unreasonable interpretations of  
legislative provisions as a “fraud on the law or a deliberate refusal to  
comply with it”, as well as being of the kind to be “treated as an act which is  
done in bad faith and is contrary to the principles of natural justice”, Beetz  
J. distinguishes such vitiating error from “a jurisdictional error” or a “mere  
error of law”.  
[185] Furthermore, immediately prior to his espousal of the foregoing rationale for  
judicial intervention in patently unreasonable decisions made within  
jurisdictional limits, he described a “mere error of law” as:  
C
an error committed by an administrative tribunal in good faith in  
interpreting or applying a provision of its enabling Act, of another  
Act, or of an agreement or other document which it has to interpret  
and apply within the limits of its jurisdiction.  
By way of parenthetical comment, it should be noted that the foregoing passage’s  
implicit endorsation of such tribunals being invested with power to make findings  
on “mere error of law” whilst “interpreting or applying a provision of its enabling  
Act” should be taken to absent authority to make findings respecting  
constitutionality of their enabling legislation’s provisions that limit their  
jurisdiction. As preceding para. 138 has pointed out, the Supreme Court of  
Canada in Cooper has held that “logic demands” tribunals have no such powers.  
What the above excerpt does settle, however, is the power of administrative bodies  
Page: 62  
to interpret general laws, and agreements or other documents, which they have “to  
interpret and apply within the limits” of their jurisdiction.  
[186] Mr. Justice Beetz’s judgment in Syndicat also provides rationale why the  
same judicial deference normally accorded to rulings of specialized  
tribunal’s made within the purview of their jurisdictional powers should  
extend to interpretation made within jurisdictional limits of legislative  
provisions. Thus at p. 441 of Syndicat, he wrote:  
C
When ... courts with a duty to exercise a superintending and  
reforming power over administrative tribunals find that an  
interpretation given by the latter to an enactment is not patently  
unreasonable, they are finding that this interpretation is defensible:  
however, they are not deciding whether the interpretation is correct or  
incorrect, and are not in general expressing any opinion on the point.  
This is exactly the approach taken by the Federal Court of Appeal in  
the case at bar, when it writes ... “even if the Board was mistaken on  
this point, it did not on that account cease to have jurisdiction over  
the matter”.  
[187] The rationale for deference that emerges from the foregoing passage is  
gleanable from its explanation that in conducting statutory interpretations  
administrative tribunals are not making pronouncements of correctness of  
legislative meaning intended for general application. Such tribunal findings  
are discrete. They are not declarations of universal application governing  
the legislative effect for all purposes of the statutory measures under arbitral  
scrutiny. They speak only to the impact of the legislation upon the  
particular dispute committed to the tribunal’s specialized knowledge, and  
thereby to the most suitable forum recognized for resolution. Hence,  
Syndicat’s message is that such tribunals have the right to be wrong, even  
in legislative interpretations made within the purview of their jurisdictional  
authority. As long as they are defensible as rulings that are not patently  
unreasonable, Beetz J.’s judgment in Syndicat makes clear that deference is  
the watchword in judicial reviews of such legislative constructions.  
>
the Paccar case:  
[188] The Supreme Court of Canada elaborated on the degree of deference to be  
observed in such judicial reviews in Caimaw v. Paccar of Canada Ltd.,  
[1989] 2 S.C.R. 983. This case is authority for treating the deference on  
judicial review of rulings within jurisdiction by administrative tribunals  
Page: 63  
involving interpretations of legislation as not just extending to errors, but to  
serious ones as long as such constructions do not transcend the bounds of  
patent unreasonableness.  
[189] Paccar addressed whether a decision of the British Columbia Labour  
Relations Board that an employer’s unilateral alteration of the terms and  
conditions of employment after termination of a collective agreement was a  
patently unreasonable interpretation of the provisions of the provincial  
Labour Code. The details of that dispute and the appeal’s outcome are not  
of immediate concern to the present discussion. However, the following  
passage from the judgment of La Forest J., whose opinion attracted  
concurrence of the majority in Paccar, provides relevant perspective of the  
high degree of deference required to be accorded to legislative  
interpretations by courts in judicial review of tribunal decisions. Thus, La  
Forest J. wrote at p. 1003 of Paccar:  
C
Where, as here, an administrative tribunal is protected by a privative  
clause, this Court has indicated it will only review the decision of the  
Board if that Board has either made an error in interpreting the  
provisions conferring jurisdiction on it, or has exceeded its  
jurisdiction by making a patently unreasonable error of law in the  
performance of its functions; see Canadian Union of Public  
Employees, Local 963 v. New Brunswick Liquor Corp., [1979] 2  
S.C.R. 227. The tribunal has the right to make errors, even serious  
ones, provided it does not act in a manner “so patently unreasonable  
that its construction cannot be rationally supported by the relevant  
legislation and demands intervention by the court upon review”.  
>
the Lester case:  
[190] Reference should also be made to Lester (W.W.) v. U.A.J.A.P.P.I., [1990]  
3 S.C.R. 644 which was an appeal from a decision of this Court. This  
appeal addressed the sustainability of a successorship declaration granted by  
the province’s Labour Relations Board pursuant to s. 89 of the Labour  
Relations Act 1977, S.N. 1977, c. 64. The purpose of that legislative  
provision was to prevent unionized employees from losing collective  
bargaining rights through dispositions of businesses by sale or transfer or by  
alterations to corporate structure. The declaration allows for the continued  
Page: 64  
effectiveness of subsisting collective agreements insofar as the bargaining  
rights of affected employees were concerned.  
[191] In Lester, the Board had applied s. 89 to a “double breasting” situation  
where, depending upon whether a job was a union or non-union  
construction site, bids on projects were submitted by companies possessing  
similar share structures and operating side by side according to the  
respective recognition or absence of collective bargaining rights. The  
Supreme Court affirmed this Court’s unanimous decision to quash the  
Board’s decision to grant the declaration on the ground that it was not  
supportable by the evidence and thus was patently unreasonable.  
[192] The significance of Lester to this discussion is the statement regarding  
judicial deference of McLachlin J., who delivered the decision of the narrow  
majority in Lester. Thus, after noting that the Newfoundland Act in s. 18  
contained a privative clause limiting judicial review to error by the Labour  
Relations Board in the performance of its functions, and referring to  
Paccar, McLachlin J. stated at p. 669:  
C
Courts should exercise caution and deference in reviewing decisions  
of specialized tribunals, such as the Labour Board in this case. This  
deference extends both to determination of the facts and the  
interpretation of the law. Only where the evidence, viewed  
reasonably, is incapable of supporting a tribunal’s findings of fact, or  
where the interpretation placed on the legislation is patently  
unreasonable, can the court interfere.  
>
overview of authorities:  
[193] The preceding four authorities establish that specialized administrative  
tribunals, such as labour relations and arbitration boards, are endowed with  
powers to interpret and apply legislation when making decisions within the  
limits of their jurisdiction. Review of such interpretative findings by these  
tribunals are not to be conducted on the basis of “mere error of law”. In  
fact, as Paccar indicates, judicial review must defer to “even serious”  
errors. Such review of legislative interpretation and application is reserved  
for indefensible patently unreasonable errors which, in Syndicat’s words,  
constitute a “fraud on the law”, and not for errors committed “in good faith”  
made whilst the tribunal was acting “within the limits of its jurisdiction”.  
Patent unreasonableness, then, is the standard of review of legislative  
meaning where, as C.U.P.E., Paccar and Lester underscore, the tribunal “is  
Page: 65  
protected from review” by a privative clause in its constituting statute. As  
ensuing discussion of the Bradco case will explain, the triggering of that  
standard has been extended to clauses which, while not explicitly stricto  
sensu privative clauses, provide for finality in arbitral decisions.  
[194] The question falling to be resolved here is whether the standard of patent  
unreasonableness applicable on judicial review of findings of general  
legislative import by labour relations boards, as laid down in C.U.P.E.,  
Syndicat, Paccar and Lester, applies equally to judicial review of the  
constitutional findings of the Arbitration Board at bar. It is true that those  
four authorities dealt with the scope of judicial review of legislative  
constructions by specialized administrative tribunals in the context of labour  
relations boards, whilst this appeal deals with findings of a labour  
arbitration board. However, that distinction is of no moment. This is  
because labour arbitration boards are also specialized administrative  
tribunals. Their existence stems from a general appreciation that disputes  
arising out of collective agreements, otherwise falling within the ambit of  
the judiciary’s powers, are better left to the specialized knowledge and  
expertise which their ad hoc creation allows to be brought to them.  
[195] The foregoing question of the patently unreasonable test’s extended  
applicability to judicial review of arbitral constitutional findings has two  
arms. The first is whether legislative limits, kindred to those that protected  
the labour relations boards’ decisions from full appellate scrutiny, likewise  
sheltered the Arbitration Board’s decision vis à vis its statutory  
interpretation of the import of s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act. If  
analysis establishes legislative limits to shelter the Arbitration Board’s  
decision, the second arm of the question is engaged. This will require  
inquiry into whether the standard of patent unreasonableness, imported to  
the judicial review process through legislative shelter of the Board’s  
decisions from full appellate scrutiny, can be applied to judicial review of  
the Board’s ultimate finding of s. 9's constitutional invalidity. As will be  
seen, this is the more difficult arm of the inquiry.  
>
the legislative factor:  
[196] It is true that labour relations boards, like many administrative tribunals, are  
created by statute which prescribe their jurisdictional limits. This contrasts  
with labour arbitration boards which are created at the disputants’ initiative  
pursuant to relevant enabling legislation to settle disputes under collective  
Page: 66  
agreements which they are called upon to interpret and apply. The standard  
of judicial review of decisions within those boards’ jurisdictional limits,  
including those entailing legislative interpretations, will be determinable  
from the enactments by which, or pursuant to which, they are created. This  
is so whether the tribunal is a labour relations, or a labour arbitration board.  
As the foregoing authorities indicate, the existence of privative clauses in  
the legislation is quite relevant to whether the standard of review is to be  
held to the deferential norm of patent unreasonableness, or the more  
stringent test of correctness.  
[197] As preceding para. 192 notes, in Lester the privative clause was in s. 18 of  
the 1977 version of the Labour Relations Act, which, while allowing the  
Labour Relations Board unrestricted latitude to review any decision made  
“by it or by the panel”, provided that otherwise “a decision or order of the  
Board is final and conclusive and not open to question or review.” This  
relatively terse wording was held sufficiently strong in Lester to trigger the  
standard of patent unreasonableness as the criterion for judicial review of  
the Board’s interpretation of the legislative provision in that case.  
>
the Bradco case:  
[198] There can be no claim of a privative clause of comparable strength in the  
case at bar. This is not conclusive, however. The Supreme Court of  
Canada, through the judgment of Sopinka J. in United Brotherhood v.  
Bradco, [1993] 2 S.C.R. 316, in setting the standard governing judicial  
review, indicated that regard should be had to what the applicable  
legislation has to say about the finality of the arbitral decision. Like Lester,  
Bradco was an appeal from this Court, and the Labour Relations Act,  
1977 was the applicable legislative source from which the standard of  
judicial review of an arbitral decision had to be settled. That time, however,  
it was not a Labour Relations Board decision protected by the strong  
privative clause which was in issue. It was rather a decision of an arbitrator,  
appointed by the parties to the dispute, pursuant to that same Act, who, to  
settle the dispute before him, was required to interpret certain provisions of  
a collective agreement precluding the hiring of non unionized workers on  
construction projects. In the course of its treatment of that issue, Bradco  
addressed the appropriate standard for judicial review of the arbitrator’s  
interpretation. It is noted that that arbitral decision was not protected by the  
Page: 67  
same privative clause as had sheltered the Labour Relations Board’s  
disposition in Lester.  
[199] Notwithstanding this lack of a true privative clause, Sopinka J. in Bradco  
found directive to apply the deferential standard of patent unreasonableness  
in s. 88(2) of the Labour Relations Act, 1977. That provision applied only  
to the construction industry and imposed a qualified regime of compulsory  
arbitration, in the absence of the parties’ agreement that a specific grievance  
may be settled by another regime, to resolve disputes and differences arising  
out of collective agreements governing relations in the construction  
industry, regardless of the manner for resolution that might have been  
prescribed in such agreements. The regime’s applicability was  
comprehensive, encompassing disputes and differences over “the  
interpretation, meaning, application or administration” of such collective  
agreements, as well as “violations” of them. The segment of s. 88(2) which  
is key in the context of the present discussion, however, was the stipulation  
that such disputes or differences “shall be submitted for final settlement to  
arbitration in accordance with this section”.  
[200] Bradco viewed those words of finality of arbitral decisions as bearing  
significant impact upon judicial review of them, and for the deference to be  
accorded to them, notwithstanding the absence of a strict privative clause.  
Sopinka J. opened his appraisal of s. 88(2) by describing it in the following  
terms in pp. 333-4 of Bradco:  
C
Section 88(2) falls somewhere between a full privative clause and a  
clause providing for full review by way of appeal. While it does not  
provide that the decision of the arbitrator is protected from review on  
any ground of law or fact, it similarly does not provide specifically  
for appeal or review on these grounds. It simply provides that the  
arbitrator’s decision will amount to final settlement of the dispute.  
The question is what the legislature intended by the use of this phrase,  
and specifically whether the phrase mandates the deference of the  
court to the particular decision made by the arbitrator in this case.  
[201] Sopinka J. then explored the legislative intent of the provision that arbitral  
dispositions would constitute final settlements of disputes, as well as the  
effect of that directive upon the deference to be accorded on judicial review.  
That inquiry’s result is expressed in p. 339 of Sopinka J’s judgment in  
Bradco which reads as follows:  
Page: 68  
C
Taking into account the relevant factors of statutory wording,  
expertise and purpose of the tribunal, I am of the opinion that the  
legislator did not intend by s. 88(2) to restrict judicial review of the  
decisions of the arbitrator except as to jurisdictional matters. Judicial  
deference to the decision of the arbitrator is nonetheless warranted  
here. In this case, the decision of the arbitrator is questioned on two  
bases: first, his conclusion that the collective agreement ... was  
unclear and ambiguous, and second, his conclusion that properly  
interpreted, Article 3.01 applied to the contract bid ... The questions  
to be resolved in coming to these conclusions involved the  
interpretation of the collective agreement and it’s application to a  
particular factual situation - - matters which constitute the core area  
of an arbitrator’s expertise. Combined with the purpose and wording  
of s. 88 which confers upon the arbitrator exclusive jurisdiction to  
come to a final settlement of disputes arising out of the interpretation  
or application of the collective agreement, the arbitrator’s relative  
expertise mandates that the court defer to the decision of the arbitrator  
in this case unless his decision is found to be patently unreasonable.  
The issue as to whether there are some decisions of an arbitrator on  
other questions of law not restricted to the interpretation of the  
collective agreement which are also immune from review may be left  
for another day.  
[202] The foregoing excerpt from Bradco affords clear and convincing  
explanation how legislative directives that arbitral decisions constitute  
“final settlement of disputes” can serve, in lieu of more explicitly strict  
privative clauses, to command deference on judicial review to those  
decisions, when made within jurisdictional limits, unless the “decision is  
found to be patently unreasonable”. With there being no such explicit  
privative clause protecting the Arbitration Board’s decision at bar, it is  
necessary to inquire whether, as was the case in Bradco, there was yet other  
legislative direction of finality signifying that “(j)udicial deference to the  
decision ... is nonetheless warranted”.  
>
the direction to deference:  
[203] The first point to be made when embarking on that inquiry is that any such  
legislative direction must come from the Public Service Collective  
Bargaining Act in pursuance to which the Arbitration Board at bar was  
Page: 69  
established. This contrasts with the situation in Bradco where the arbitrator  
was appointed under the provisions of the Labour Relations Act. This  
distinction is, nevertheless, one without substantial difference in the context  
of the standard of judicial review of arbitral decisions rendered under either  
statute. This is because of the kindred manner in which both enactments  
conferred on the respective arbitration processes “exclusive jurisdiction to  
come to a final settlement of disputes”, and thereby impressed the  
deferential standard of the patently unreasonable test on judicial review of  
their findings.  
[204] The relevant section of the Public Service Collective Bargaining Act  
which impressed finality upon decisions of arbitration boards established in  
pursuant to it is s. 39(1). That section confers the exclusive jurisdiction of  
final settlement in the following terms:  
C
A collective agreement which does not contain provisions for final  
settlement, by arbitration or otherwise, of all differences between the  
parties to or persons bound by the agreement or on whose behalf it  
was entered into, where those differences arise out of the  
interpretation, application or administration or alleged violation of the  
collective agreement, including a question as to whether a matter is  
arbitrable, shall be considered to contain those provisions set out in  
subsection 86(2) of the Labour Relations Act.  
[205] The foregoing provision, effectively conferring the status of finality on  
public sector arbitral rulings, tracks substantially word for word s. 86 of the  
Labour Relations Act’s conferment of similar status on arbitral rulings  
arising out of collective agreements in the private sector. Both provide that  
where collective agreements contain no provisions for final settlements of  
all differences arising within the recognizable limits of arbitral jurisdiction,  
such collective agreements “shall be considered to contain” the provisions  
set out in s. 86(2) of the Labour Relations Act which provide for the  
establishment and procedures of an arbitration board to arbitrate disputes.  
In each case, the decisions of such boards are, under s. 86(2)(f), “final and  
binding” upon the parties and upon a person on whose behalf” the collective  
agreement was made. It was, then, through its incorporation of “subsection  
86(2) of the Labour Relations Act” that s. 39(1) of the Public Service  
Collective Bargaining Act conferred upon the arbitral process established  
under it “exclusive jurisdiction to come to a final settlement of disputes”.  
Page: 70  
[206] Bradco stands as incontrovertible authority for applying the standard of  
patent unreasonableness to judicial review of rulings of arbitration boards  
made within jurisdictional limits where a direction to deference can be  
found in their constituting legislation. The direction to the deferential  
standard may be found either in privative legislative clauses protecting the  
arbitral dispositions from review, or in legislative provisions which confer,  
in Bradco’s words reproduced in preceding para. 201, “exclusive  
jurisdiction to come to a final settlement of disputes arising out of the  
interpretation or application of the collective agreement”.  
[207] In Bradco the “final” ruling was made by an arbitrator, constituted pursuant  
to s. 88 of the 1977 version of the Labour Relations Act (now s. 92 in the  
current 1990 revised version) to settle a dispute arising out of the  
interpretation and application of a collective agreement in the construction  
industry. The dispute was over the meaning of a provision in the collective  
agreement dealing with rights of employees on construction sites.  
[208] In contrast, the ruling at bar was made by an Arbitration Board constituted  
in pursuance of s. 39 of the Public Service Collective Bargaining Act to  
settle a dispute arising out of collective agreements dealing with rights of  
employees in the public sector. The gravamen of the dispute at bar focuses  
on the impact of s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act in its application  
upon Government’s obligations to make the pay equity adjustments under  
those collective agreements. The dispute, therefore, entails statutory  
interpretation of a legislative measure, and the application of the resultant  
construction to the collective agreements, rather than straight construction  
and application of those agreements themselves which was the situation in  
Bradco.  
[209] As to these differences, the fact that the arbitration processes at bar and in  
Bradco were conducted under the authority of different enactments is  
neither here nor there. In the first place, it is not strictly accurate to  
maintain they were conducted under different statutory provisions. As  
already explained in preceding para. 205, s. 39(1) of the Arbitration Board’s  
constituent legislation incorporates s. 86 of the Labour Relations Act into  
the arbitral process, and made s. 86 applicable to disputes arising out of  
public sector collective agreements. In fact, this Arbitration Board derives  
its commission “to come to a final settlement of disputes” from that  
referential incorporation. Thus, the determinant of the standard of judicial  
review lies in the finality of decision that applied to the arbitral rulings both  
Page: 71  
in Bradco and at bar. Moreover, the finality of decision actually emanates  
from the same source in both instances i.e., the Labour Relations Act.  
[210] Hence, although the arbitrations were conducted under different enactments,  
judicial review of dispositions within jurisdictional limits of the Arbitration  
Board at bar, as well as those of the arbitrator in Bradco, both were  
ultimately directed by the curial deference that triggers the patently  
unreasonable standard of judicial review through conferrals of exclusive  
jurisdiction to come to final settlements of disputes in both instances under  
the Labour Relations Act. It is true that it is the general provisions of  
private sector arbitration in s-s. 86(2) of that Act which are engrafted into  
the public sector arbitral process, whilst the arbitration in Bradco was  
conducted under subsisting s-s. 92(2) of that Act, which is made specifically  
applicable to the construction industry. However, as already underscored,  
the watchword insofar as the appropriate standard of judicial review is  
concerned is the finality of decision, and there is no doubt that the  
Arbitration Board at bar was invested with exclusive jurisdiction to make  
final dispositions under the legislation applicable to it. Hence, no  
significance should be attached to the fact that the respective arbitrations at  
bar and in Bradco were conducted under separate statutes.  
[211] Neither is it of any consequence that the Arbitration Board at bar was  
engaged in legislative interpretation of the impact of s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act and the application of its construction to the  
collective agreements, rather than straight interpretation and application of  
those collective agreements as was the arbitration in Bradco. The  
dispositions in C.U.P.E., Syndicat, Paccar and Lester give ample room to  
conclude that legislative interpretations for application to collective  
agreements lie within the competence of arbitration boards, just as do  
interpretations within the confines of such agreements with which the  
judicial review in Bradco was occupied. It is true that these  
aforementioned four authorities addressed judicial reviews of legislative  
constructions of labour relations boards within their statutory mandates. It  
is equally quite clear from a perusal of those four authorities, however, that  
those dispositions wielded a wider brush inasmuch as the labour relations  
boards, whose decisions were sought to be reviewed, were referred to from  
time to time as administrative boards and specialized tribunals, amongst  
which arbitration boards of the type engaged in this appeal are numbered as  
well.  
Page: 72  
[212] The distinctions, therefore, are not material to the application of Bradco to  
the appropriate standard of judicial review in the circumstances at bar.  
Accordingly, on the footing of the direction to deference which the relevant  
legislation effectively enjoins judicial reviews of public sector arbitral  
decisions to observe, and on the basis of the authoritative recognition that  
legislative interpretation lies within the ambit of such arbitral decision-  
making powers, it is concluded, on the combined authority of all five  
dispositions, that the standard of judicial review of the interpretation that  
the law sets for the Arbitration Board’s interpretation of s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act is patent unreasonableness.  
[213] In the result, the first arm of the question posed in preceding para. 195 is  
resolvable in the affirmative. There are legislative limits relating to judicial  
review incorporated into the Arbitration Board’s constituent statute, kindred  
to those that protected the labour relations boards, whose decisions were  
under scrutiny in C.U.P.E., Syndicat, Paccar and Lester, that shelter from  
full review by way of appeal the Board’s decision regarding the impact of s.  
9 of the restraint legislation on the dispute arising out of the collective  
agreements before it. This being the case, it is clear that patent  
unreasonableness is the test that had to be applied in judicial review of the  
Board’s statutory interpretation of s. 9 which is yet to be broached in this  
judgment. However, the immediate and more difficult concern is whether  
that test also applies to the Board’s constitutional findings vis à vis s. 9's  
application to the dispute before it. At this point, the discussion proceeds to  
the second arm of the question set out in preceding para. 195, i.e., whether  
the same standard of patent unreasonableness, extends to judicial review of  
the Board’s constitutional findings.  
>
constitutional deference:  
[214] At first blush, it would appear there is strong reason to respond  
affirmatively to that question. After all, the Board was still occupied with  
interpreting s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act, albeit in the context of  
its compliance with the Charter insofar as it affected the dispute under  
arbitration. There would seem no reason why the direction to deference  
mandated through the Public Sector Collective Bargaining Act should not  
apply to legislative interpretations involving applications of the Charter,  
nor why the patently unreasonable standard of judicial review laid down in  
C.U.P.E., Syndicat, Paccar and Lester should not be equally engaged in  
Page: 73  
judicial review of constitutional applications by public sector arbitration  
boards, such as the one at bar.  
[215] As preceding para. 109 has already noted, La Forest J. held in Chuddy  
Chicks that a tribunal having “jurisdiction over the whole of the matter”,  
which this judgment has already concluded the Arbitration Board in this  
case had, acts within the limits of that jurisdiction in addressing “a Charter  
issue”. In so doing, it would seem to follow logically that this power  
includes authority to interpret and apply the Charter, as arbitration Boards  
do, in the context of other legislative enactments in valid exercise of their  
exclusive jurisdiction to settle dispute arising out of collective agreements.  
After all, as McLachlin J. states in her judgment, albeit a dissenting one, at  
para. 70 of Cooper:  
C
The Charter is not some holy grail which only judicial initiates of the  
superior courts may touch. The Charter belongs to the people. All  
law and law-makers that touch the people must conform to it.  
Tribunals and commissions charged with deciding legal issues are no  
exception. Many more citizens have their rights determined by these  
tribunals than by the courts. If the Charter is to be meaningful to  
ordinary people, then it must find its expression in the decisions of  
these tribunals ... if Parliament confers on the tribunal the power to  
decide questions of law, that power must, in the absence of counter-  
indications, be taken to extend to the Charter, and to the question of  
whether the Charter renders portions of its enabling statute  
unconstitutional.  
[216] The closing words of the foregoing passage earmark McLachlin J.’s dissent  
from La Forest J.’s majority judgment in Cooper. They evince  
disagreement with the latter’s holding in para. 139 of that case that neither a  
tribunal appointed by the Canadian Human Rights Commission, nor the  
Commission itself, was empowered to determine the constitutional validity  
of its enabling statute. While the entire excerpt is directed towards that area  
of disagreement, if the last phrase be deleted from the passage, the  
remainder might be taken as support for a standard of patent  
unreasonableness in judicial review of Charter interpretations and  
applications by arbitration boards within their jurisdictional limits.  
Nevertheless, shortly before, the Supreme Court of Canada, through La  
Forest J.’s judgment in Douglas College, had explicitly held that  
correctness, not patent unreasonableness, is the applicable standard of  
Page: 74  
judicial review of Charter applications made within the ambit of arbitral  
competence. Thus, at p. 605 of Douglas College, La Forest J. wrote:  
C
... I think it important that those called upon to make governmental  
decision focus on the values enshrined in the Charter. I should add  
that constitutional determinations by arbitrators or other  
administrative tribunals or agencies should, of course, receive no  
curial deference .... They are not there acting within the limits of their  
expertise.  
[217] There are actually three arguments enlistable in support of not observing  
curial deference, and the concomitant standard of patent unreasonableness,  
in judicial review of arbitral Charter determinations. The first is the limits  
of expertise in arbitration or other administrative tribunals, which has just  
been mentioned in the foregoing passage from Douglas College. The  
second flows from a view that admitting the curial deference of patent  
unreasonableness to the judicial review process would be tantamount to a  
usurpation of the courts’ powers, and a disruption of fundamental principles  
of democratic parliamentary government. This second position is based on  
the extendability of Lamer C.J.C.’s concurrence with La Forest J.’s majority  
disposition in Cooper, wherein the former Chief Justice put forth a case for  
judicial monopoly over constitutional rulings. The third argument is based  
upon the importance of constitutional challenges to the validity of  
legislation. Attention will now focus in turn upon each of these arguments  
that militate against observing curial deference in respect of constitutional  
findings of administrative tribunals, which include labour arbitrations such  
as the one whose constitutional ruling is under scrutiny in the appeal at bar.  
>
the expertise argument:  
[218] As already explained, supportive authority for rejecting curial deference  
comes out of the extract from Douglas College reproduced in preceding  
para. 216. However, it must be noted that this conclusion appears  
somewhat at variance with the specialized nature of arbitration boards. This  
was recognized by La Forest J. who made specific reference to this attribute  
in pp. 604-605 of his judgment, immediately preceding his comment that the  
limits of their expertise foreclosed curial deference to arbitral Charter  
rulings. Thus, before making that comment, he had just mentioned “the  
advantages of the expertise of the arbitrator or agency”, whilst noting that  
“(t)hat specialized competence can be of invaluable assistance in  
Page: 75  
constitutional interpretations”. On their face, these remarks appear at odds  
with his ensuing comment that “constitutional determinations” were outside  
“the limits of their expertise”, and this should receive “no curial deference”  
on judicial review.  
[219] This aspect of La Forest J.’s judgment in Douglas College is not singled out  
in an attempt at demonstrating inconsistency. It is clear from a perusal of  
the entire commentary preceding the conclusion that “no curial deference”  
should be accorded on review of arbitral constitutional findings that the  
existence of strong arguments to the contrary was recognized, and Mr.  
Justice La Forest was acknowledging the conclusion at which he arrived had  
been a difficult one to draw. The highlighted comments culminating in the  
limited expertise conclusion drawn in Douglas College are, then, rather  
illustrative of the narrowness of that call.  
[220] At the same time, it has to be observed, nonetheless, that it appears  
somewhat problematic to hold no curial deference should be extended by  
courts in the exercise of their superintending and reforming power over  
constitutional findings of arbitrators, who have been accorded exclusive  
jurisdiction to come to final settlements, and who are recognized to have  
“specialized competence ... in constitutional interpretation”. From this  
standpoint, it seems apropos to wonder why such arbitral constitutional  
findings should be denied the protection of the same deferential standard of  
patent unreasonableness that shelter other legislative interpretations when  
applied to disputes arising out of collective agreements.  
[221] Perhaps the explanation may lie in the assertion that the specialized  
competence can be of “invaluable assistance”. In other words, the expertise  
can be viewed as invaluable in assisting proper constitutional interpretation  
made in the course of the exercise of exclusive jurisdiction to bring final  
settlement to disputes under collective agreements. However, given the  
importance of constitutional questions, labour arbitration boards should  
have no right to be wrong as they do in construing other legislation. Thus,  
ultimate determination of the sustainability of constitutional rulings must lie  
with the courts on the standard of correctness. This really appears to be the  
nub of the correctness standard’s rationale.  
[222] The unavoidable conclusion that emerges from this analysis is that the  
notion of lack of expertise of arbitrators as justification for application of  
the correctness standard in judicial review of arbitral constitutional findings  
rests on tenuous ground in light of the acknowledged “specialized  
Page: 76  
competence ... in constitutional matters” of arbitration boards entrusted with  
power to make such rulings. Advocating the importance of Charter  
findings in justification of the correctness standard, as will presently be  
explained, runs afoul of McLachlin J.’s “holy grail” comment in Cooper.  
Before entering that phase of the discussion, however, focus will converge  
on the second argument against extending curial deference to arbitral  
constitutional rulings.  
>
the usurpation argument:  
[223] The usurpation argument rests on the view that according curial deference  
to Charter findings of arbitration tribunals would infringe fundamental  
features of the Constitution. This premise is supported by remarks of Lamer  
C.J.C. in his concurring judgment in Cooper, where he decried incursion of  
administrative tribunals into the constitutional field which he viewed as  
properly lying within the judiciary’s exclusive preserve. Indeed, as the first  
paragraph of his judgment in Cooper records, Lamer C.J.C. went as far as  
to express the hope that “a full bench of this Court will eventually have the  
opportunity to revisit the proposition”. The “proposition” to which Lamer  
C.J.C. refers is the holding of the Supreme Court of Canada in Cooper and  
other authorities that administrative bodies empowered to apply any law  
necessary to reach its findings, including general legislation, likewise had  
jurisdiction to apply the Charter.  
[224] Actually, Lamer C.J.C.’s judgment in Cooper was not directed to the  
general subject of curial deference to arbitral constitutional rulings, which  
this appeal engages. As preceding para. 138 records, the issue in Cooper  
was whether an administrative tribunal had jurisdiction to question the  
constitutional validity of a provision of its enabling statute. Thus, Lamer  
C.J.C.’s words, as were those of McLachlin J. in her dissent in that same  
case, were really directed to that issue. While Lamer C.J.C. sided with the  
result of La Forest J.’s judgment in Cooper, and associated with the holding  
that those tribunals lacked jurisdiction to pass upon their own enabling  
powers, he took the occasion to strongly question whether such bodies  
should be empowered to make constitutional findings at all. In so doing, he  
advocated the Court revisit its stance to the contrary in Chuddy Chicks,  
Douglas College and Weber, as well as other authorities in similar vein,  
including Tétreault-Gadoury v. Canada (E.I.C.), [1991] 2 S.C.R. 22.  
Page: 77  
[225] Lamer C.J.C.’s reasoning in that regard has been the subject of academic  
commentaries. Amongst them are: J. McMillan, “Tribunals and the  
Charter: The Search for Implied Jurisdiction - A Case Comment on  
Cooper v. Canada (Human Rights Commission)”, (1998) 32 U.B.C. L.  
Rev. 365; M.C. Crane, “Administrative Tribunals, Charter Challenges,  
and the Web of Institutional Relationships”, (1998) 61 Sask. L. Rev. 495;  
and K. Tabbakh, “The Standard of Review of Grievance Arbitrators  
When Deciding on Human Rights Issues: The “Magnificent Goal” v.  
Industrial Peace”, (1998) 43 McGill L.J. 261. Detailed treatment of those  
articles lies outside this discussion’s purview. In para. 62 of Ms. Crane’s  
article, she notes that Lamer C.J.C.’s claim in Cooper for judicial monopoly  
over constitutional interpretation and applications provides “fodder” for  
extensive analysis. This is so in the present context as well, where his thesis  
of usurpation of the judiciary’s preserve is being assessed as extendable  
argument for application of the correctness standard on judicial review of  
arbitral constitutional findings.  
[226] In so assessing the extendability of that argument, it should be recognized  
the former Chief Justice’s viewpoint of usurpation of judicial monopoly was  
a dissenting one, notwithstanding its expression in a judgment siding with  
the majority result in Cooper. Thus, just as McLachlin’s “holy grail”  
passage reproduced in preceding para. 215 will be evaluated presently in  
assessment of the logic of curial deference being accorded on judicial  
review to arbitral Charter findings, so too the usurpation viewpoint of  
Lamer C.J.C., also expressed in Cooper, will be similarly enlisted. Given  
that both offerings were voiced as dissenting opinions, this judgment is free  
to bask in the latitude normally enjoyed by academia of either adopting one  
opinion or the other, or rejecting both of them, insofar as their respective  
impact on this discussion on curial deference and appropriate standard of  
review is concerned.  
[227] Moreover, insofar as Lamer C.J.C.’s argument for judicial monopoly over  
constitutional findings is extendable to the appropriate standard of judicial  
review of Charter findings of labour arbitration boards, this judgment  
contents itself by and large with endorsing the commentaries proffered in  
the three articles highlighted in preceding para. 225 on the position taken by  
the former Chief Justice. There are, however, several observations that need  
be made regarding the unextendability of that argument as support for the  
Page: 78  
premise that no curial deference should be accorded to arbitral  
constitutional findings.  
[228] The argument for judicial monopoly is erected upon perceived disruption of  
relationships between the three branches of government, established under  
the Separation of Powers Doctrine, as it operates within the democratic  
Parliamentary System of government, which Doctrine and System Lamer  
C.J.C. describes as “defining features of the Canadian Constitution” (see  
paras. 10 and 22 of Cooper). Affirming no intent to detract “from the  
general duty to interpret statutes in light of Charter values” (para. 21), he  
nonetheless saw the authority conferred on administrative tribunals to  
declare law of no force and effect under s. 52 of the Constitution Act as  
reason to “strongly urge my colleagues to revisit those decisions in order to  
ensure the Charter does not distort the deep structure of the Canadian  
Constitution” (para. 29). As already underscored, the Doctrine and the  
System, the two “defining features” to which he adverted, were embedded  
in the Constitution as integral underpinnings of that “deep structure”.  
[229] In relating Lamer C.J.C.’s statement in Cooper to the circumstances at bar,  
it is difficult to see how such a distortion would be perpetrated by observing  
curial deference with respect to constitutional interpretations of labour  
arbitrators, and to consequential applications by them of s. 52 of the  
Constitution Act. After all, if the authorities affirm, as they do, that  
judicial review of general legislative rulings by administrative bodies,  
including labour arbitration boards, can be undertaken on the standard of  
patent unreasonableness without being violative of the Separation of Powers  
Doctrine and the Parliamentary System embedded in the Constitution, it  
would appear to follow logically that the same standard should apply to  
judicial review of legislative interpretations of Charter compliance by such  
boards without infringing the Constitution, or either of the highlighted  
defining features embedded in it, unless there be something peculiar to the  
Charter precluding the analogy.  
[230] Moreover, continuing to speak in the terms of labour arbitration boards with  
which this appeal is concerned, but not necessarily foreclosing extension of  
the discussion to other administrative bodies, it is difficult to comprehend  
how the relationships between the three branches of government within the  
Parliamentary System, would be disturbed if applications of s. 52 by labour  
arbitrators to legislation affecting disputes were reviewable on the  
deferential standard of patent unreasonableness. In the first place, findings  
Page: 79  
of such arbitrators in that regard are discrete. They do not constitute general  
declarations of invalidity of legislation. In exercise of their recognized  
“specialized competence ... in constitutional interpretation”, which  
preceding para. 220 records the Supreme Court of Canada to have  
acknowledged through La Forest J.’s judgment in Cooper, they merely  
declare the legislative provisions in question (in this case s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act) to be of no effect in the particular disputes arising  
out of the collective agreements before the arbitrators. As is the case with  
the argument of lack of expertise, it is difficult to see how extension of  
curial deference to such arbitral decisions would any more run afoul of  
Constitutional precepts than would other legislative applications, unless  
there is something peculiar to Charter rulings making the analogy inapt.  
[231] In addressing this question of the usurpation argument’s extendability to the  
judicial review standard now under discussion, it is important to bear in  
mind that it is not always possible to distinguish functionally with precision  
between the powers of the three branches of government. In the context of  
the present discussion it is also important to underscore that the tenets of the  
Separation of Powers doctrine do not confer a monopoly upon the judiciary  
to interpret and apply the law. These points are made in the following  
extract from the text of the eminent British constitutional scholar, Sir W.  
Ivor Jennings, entitled “The Law and the Constitution”, 4th ed.,  
(University of London Press, 1952) in commenting upon the operation of  
the Separation of Powers Doctrine within the Parliamentary System of  
government. That text reads thusly at pp. 24-25:  
C
There are characteristics of various classes of functions which make it  
desirable that they should, for instance, be exercised by independent  
judges; but there is no single characteristic or group of characteristics  
which enables the legislature to determine out of hand that a  
particular function should be assigned to judges, or, in other words,  
which distinguish “judicial” classes of functions .... It is necessary to  
have at least three classes of authorities, but they are distinguished  
rather by their composition or their methods than by characteristics of  
their functions.  
[232] It is not to be suggested that Lamer C.J.C.’s judgment in Cooper failed to  
recognize that the powers of the respective branches of government are not  
able to be pigeon-holed neatly on functional bases. At the outset of his  
discussion of the Doctrine in his judgment in Cooper, at para. 10, he wrote:  
Page: 80  
“the separation of powers under the Canadian Constitution is not strict in  
that judicial functions, including the interpretation of law, may be vested in  
non-judicial bodies such as tribunals ...”. His thesis is rather that “non-  
judicial bodies”, which would include labour arbitration tribunals, should  
not be invested with the function of interpreting and applying constitutional  
law, notwithstanding their “general duty to interpret statutes in light of  
Charter values”.  
[233] That thesis is constructed on a role seen to be assigned to the judiciary in the  
Separation of Powers, as that Doctrine operates within a Parliamentary  
System of government. This role is essentially a policing one in which the  
judiciary is perceived as being called upon to protect its primary mission of  
interpreting and applying the law from incursions by the legislative and  
executive branches of government, which are portrayed as normally bent on  
such ends for the purpose of aggrandizements of their own powers through  
appropriations of those within the judiciary’s purview. This perception of  
the judiciary as enforcer of the separation of powers, and protector of its  
own judicial authority within its relationships with the two other branches  
of government, clearly emerges from a passage in Lamer C.J.C.’s discussion  
of the Separation of Powers Doctrine, and in his ensuing interpretation of an  
observation from an eminent Canadian constitutional law scholar. It should  
also be noted that this perception likewise clearly surfaces in the majority  
judgment of the case addressing references respecting the impact of public  
sector restraints upon Provincial Court judges in Prince Edward Island and  
Manitoba, captioned as: Re Provincial Court Judges, [1997] 3 S.C.R. 3 to  
which subsequent reference will be made in ensuing para. 347. The relevant  
passage in Cooper is contained in para. 13 of that case which reads:  
C
The constitutional status of the judiciary, flowing as it does  
from the separation of powers, requires that certain functions be  
exclusively exercised by judicial bodies. Although the judiciary  
certainly does not have an interpretative monopoly over questions of  
law, in my opinion, it must have exclusive jurisdiction over  
challenges to the validity of legislation under the Constitution of  
Canada, and particularly the Charter. The reason is that only courts  
have the requisite independence to be entrusted with the  
constitutional scrutiny of legislation when that scrutiny leads a court  
to declare invalid an enactment of the legislature. Mere Creatures of  
the legislature, whose very existence can be terminated at the stroke  
Page: 81  
of a legislative pen, whose members, while the tribunal is in  
existence, usually serve at the pleasure of the government of the day,  
and whose decisions in some circumstances are properly governed by  
guidelines established by the executive branch of government, are not  
suited to this task. ...  
[234] The clear thrust of this argument for judicial monopoly over constitutional  
challenges to the validity of legislation is that only the courts are invested  
with the necessary independence to be “entrusted” with such commissions;  
and, to ward off usurpation of the powers allotted to the judiciary through  
the Separation of Powers Doctrine by misuse of the parliamentary  
supremacy endemic in the Parliamentary System of government. That in a  
nutshell is the kernel of the usurpation argument.  
[235] Subsequently, in para. 16, the judgment finds reinforcement for its argument  
by enlisting the following commentary from Professor Peter Hogg’s text  
entitled Constitutional Law of Canada, 3rd ed. (Toronto: Carswell, 1991)  
at p. 168:  
C
The independence of the judge from the other branches of  
government is especially significant because it provides an assurance  
that the state will be subjected to the rule of law. If the state could  
count on the courts to ratify all legislative and executive actions, even  
if authorized by law, the individual would have no protection against  
tyranny. (Emphasis added by Lamer C.J.C.)  
[236] Certainly, no exception may be taken with the assertion, which was made  
prior to the enlistment of the foregoing commentary from Professor Hogg’s  
text, that a society governed by the rule of law requires a judicial system  
which can assure its orders are enforced and its process respected. Nor may  
the notion, earlier endorsed by Lamer C.J.C., be disabused that judicial  
independence is essential to maintain the rule of law, and to assure the  
integrity of the judicial system’s process remains unimpaired. The  
Separation of Powers Doctrine supports these fundamental tenets. In so  
doing, however, that Doctrine envisages no jurisdictional battleground in  
which the judiciary is portrayed as the protector of its powers against  
tyrannous misuse of legislative supremacy within the Parliamentary System  
of government.  
[237] Such a portrayal does not fit well the view that legislative bodies are  
presumed to intend to act within their jurisdictional powers in enacting  
legislation. This is the approach that has always been taken in judicial  
Page: 82  
assessments of the constitutional validity of legislation in face of claims that  
one order of government has intruded on the other’s prerogatives allotted  
under division of powers in ss. 91 and 92 of the Constitution. It is likewise  
the proper course to be taken in judicial assessments of legislative  
compatibility with Charter values. It is similarly the approach in judicial  
assessments of complaints of legislative incursions by the political branches  
of government upon the judiciary’s role assigned to it under the Separation  
of Powers Doctrine. That Doctrine should not be viewed as prescribing  
rules of conduct in a jurisdictional conflict in which the judiciary is arrayed  
as protector of its jurisdiction against the tyrannical elected branches, which  
are seen as bent on trampling on the powers reserved to the courts, and on  
denying individual liberties protected by the rule of law. This would be a  
rather dismal view of that “defining feature of the Canadian Constitution”.  
It is not one that is endorsed in the writings of constitutional scholars.  
[238] The foregoing extract from Professor Hogg’s text reproduced in preceding  
para. 235 does not reflect endorsation of that viewpoint. It is true the  
passage speaks of judicial independence as essential protection against  
individual tyranny. However, the statement should be taken as historical  
reflection on the function of judicial independence within the Separation of  
Powers Doctrine and, in that light, on its contemporary role as assurer of the  
rule of law and protector of individual fundamental rights and liberties from  
inadvertent incursions by executive and legislative actions. It is an  
undeniable fact that the precept of judicial independence was honed as an  
antidote to despotic incursions upon fundamental freedoms. It is equally  
true that judicial independence evolved to play a vital role in the democratic  
operation of the Parliamentary System of government. However, Professor  
Hogg’s commentary does not appear to suggest advertence to the Separation  
of Powers Doctrine should be approached in contemporary times on the  
footing of the jurisdictional battlefield which is implicit in the usurpation  
argument.  
[239] The principles of that Doctrine, which include the judiciary’s independence,  
combine to provide a vital, but delicate, balance of power within the state  
which is accomplished by practical application of the Doctrine’s delineation  
of the composition and functions of the three main branches of government.  
While it is the judiciary’s duty to protect individual liberties, the courts  
shoulder equal responsibility in so doing to be vigilant not to impinge  
inadvertently upon the prerogatives of the other governmental branches,  
Page: 83  
particularly through undue intrusions into their policy-making roles. The  
mission of the judiciary within the context of the Separation of Powers  
Doctrine, therefore, is to maintain the balance embedded in that “defining  
feature of the Canadian Constitution” between the legislative, executive and  
judicial branches of government. It is acknowledged that in acquitting this  
task the courts will be frequently required to provide reasoned defences of  
their own powers. However, with all due respect, depicting the courts as  
guardians of the people against despotic exercise of arbitrary power, which  
the usurpation argument advances, places out of proper focus the operation  
of the Separation of Powers Doctrine within the Parliamentary System.  
Besides, such portrayals would not appear to be especially conducive to  
facilitating the integration of Charter values into applications of the general  
body of law.  
[240] For the foregoing reasons, this judgment does not side with the usurpation  
argument’s case for judicial monopoly over constitutional challenges to  
legislation. With due respect to its proponents, neither the Separation of  
Powers Doctrine, not the Charter’s advent within the Parliamentary  
System, justify the usurpation argument’s case for exclusive jurisdiction in  
the courts over rulings on the constitutional validity of legislation. This  
being so, it appears to follow as natural corollary, that that argument is not  
extendable in justification of correctness as the standard of judicial review  
of constitutional rulings by such administrative tribunals and, more  
particularly in the context of this appeal, by labour arbitration boards.  
>
the importance argument:  
[241] In light of rejection of the foregoing arguments, the logic of the case for  
judicial monopoly over rulings upon constitutional challenges to the validity  
of legislation and executive actions, or, concomitantly, for application of the  
correctness standard on judicial review of such rulings by non-curial  
tribunals if endowed with jurisdiction in the constitutional field, will have to  
rest on the importance of those rulings.  
[242] In broaching that argument, it must first be acknowledged that there is no  
way to gainsay the importance of Charter rulings to contemporary society.  
The Charter placed in the hands of individual citizens an effective means  
of enforcing their basic rights and liberties, the recognition of the  
fundamental values of which has long earmarked a distinction between  
democratic and totalitarian states. As such, it can legitimately be said to  
Page: 84  
have had a revolutionary impact on the Canadian federation by tempering  
the parliamentary supremacy of the respective orders of government to the  
extent that laws and actions can be declared inoperative because they  
demonstrably violate guaranteed fundamental individual rights in a manner  
unjustifiable in a free and democratic society.  
[243] Prior to the Charter’s advent, the individual whose fundamental rights were  
so affected by laws of general application or administrative actions under  
them had no effective means of enforcing the basic rights that were being  
trampled upon. His or her only recourse was to petition to Parliament or the  
Legislature where even entreaties for relief that fell on sympathetic ears  
would normally be subsumed by the countervailing social interests that  
prompted the impugned measure or action in the first place. Within the  
parameters set out in it, the Charter accords supremacy to individual rights  
over societal interests, provided the paramountcy is justifiable in a free and  
democratic society. It gives expression to the primacy of fundamental rights  
guaranteed under it by enabling individuals to effectively enforce them  
through the judicial process.  
[244] As dramatic as that reform was, it needs to be borne in mind that the  
Charter did not create the fundamental rights and freedoms it guarantees.  
They are of a much more ancient lineage. Moreover, laws and  
governmental actions were formulated and authorized in sensibility of the  
values embodied in those rights and liberties entrenched in the Charter  
long before its conception. It is, therefore, not to be supposed that its  
framers could, or did, purport to have invented those fundamental rights and  
liberties on the Charter’s proclamation. The new constitutional mechanism  
for enforcing fundamental rights rather addressed individual impotence in  
the face of encroachments upon them by providing a means of their  
protection through the courts to the extent that their exercise in the specific  
circumstances obtaining could be shown reasonable in a free and democratic  
society.  
[245] In strengthening the judiciary’s role as protector of those individual rights,  
the Charter reflects recognition by the political branches of government  
within the Canadian federation that, in balancing individual and societal  
interests, the state’s laws and actions may inadvertently transgress  
individual freedoms, in a manner not theretofore contemplated by the  
governing authority, that is incompatible with the underlying tenets of a free  
and democratic society. The strengthened role of the judiciary speaks to the  
Page: 85  
reality that it is difficult to foresee all of the consequences in formulating  
laws of general application, and to a policy of according paramountcy to  
individual fundamental rights that were untenably breached in that process.  
Thus, the protective role with which the courts were cloaked by the Charter  
envisaged shielding individuals from unintended consequences of  
unacceptable incursions on fundamental rights and liberties. It is through  
that role that the guarantee of those rights and liberties was secured.  
However, it is important to recognize the role is one of protection against  
inadvertent incursions. It is not one of guardian against advertent  
encroachments by unscrupulous governments bent on manipulations for  
their own political machinations. Such a cynical portrayal of the court’s  
role imports a wrong perspective to the Charter, and is hardly conducive to  
recognition and acceptance of the beneficial reforms wrought by it.  
[246] It should also be noted in passing that the concept of individual access to  
courts to challenge the validity of laws is not novel. Laws of both orders of  
government have been subject to individual challenge for want of vires  
under either s. 91 or s. 92 since the inception of the Canadian federation. A  
true perspective of the Charter is that it added another arrow to the quiver  
of the individual’s arsenal broadening the scope of challenge to laws and  
actions of the legislative and executive arms of government. This  
observation in no way detracts from the importance of the Charter. The  
greater protection it accords to basic fundamental rights and freedoms, and  
its tempering of the powers of the political branches of government in its  
redefining of long-established concepts of parliamentary supremacy, herald  
reforms of no insignificant moment.  
[247] That said, the present inquiry addresses whether the importance of the  
Charter is such that rulings made under it should rest within the exclusive  
purview of the courts; and, alternately if not, whether the correctness  
standard should apply on judicial review of such rulings. As to the first  
question, the words of McLachlin J. in Cooper, reproduced in preceding  
para. 215, are quite apropos. Despite the undeniable importance of the  
Charter, as she said in Cooper, it “is not some holy grail which only  
judicial initiatives of the superior courts may touch”. Yet, hyperbolic  
portrayals of the Charter that have sometimes seem to depict the Charter  
as a latter day holy grail from which fundamental freedoms assured under  
the supreme law of the land are handed down under the aegis of initiatives  
of the judiciary.  
Page: 86  
[248] In addressing this question of whether Charter rulings are of such  
importance that the judiciary should have the monopoly to make them, it is  
well to bear in mind that administrative bodies often address the values  
embodied in fundamental rights when interpreting and applying legislation.  
In the instance at bar, for example, apart from the constitutional question,  
the Arbitration Board was called upon to decide whether government’s  
obligation for the retroactive pay equity adjustments had been legislatively  
extinguished. In so doing, it was dealing with a fundamental right of female  
employees to be treated in a non-discriminatory manner. Having dealt with  
that fundamental right in one context, it seems reasonable that the same  
tribunal should be entitled to treat them in another. As important as  
Charter rights indisputably are, they have no mystical attributes. Their  
underlying values are well appreciated by most. This is why they are styled  
as fundamental. The members of administrative bodies seem just as capable  
of appreciating the values expressed in them as they are the often more  
technical and complex concepts of ordinary legislation which are within  
their well-settled powers to interpret and apply.  
[249] Accordingly, notwithstanding the importance of Charter rulings, there is  
sound reason to support administrative bodies being empowered to address  
Charter issues in disposing of matters within their jurisdictional limits.  
There is, as has already been noted, ample authority for such empowerment  
in Chuddy Chicks, Douglas College, Weber and Tétreault-Gadoury.  
[250] Having resolved that, on reason and authority, the judiciary has no  
monopoly over Charter rulings, it would appear that the same reasoning  
lends a sense of logic to judicial reviews of such rulings being conducted on  
the patent unreasonableness standard which the authorities endorse as the  
test of statutory interpretations by administrative tribunals. As important as  
those rulings be, they too are statutory interpretations made by specialized  
tribunals which are discrete in the sense and, as preceding para. 163 notes  
Chuddy Chicks has held, do not extend to “formal declaration(s) of  
invalidity”. However, as preceding para. 216 goes on to note, Douglas  
College has unequivocally held that Charter rulings by arbitrators or  
administrative tribunals should not receive curial deference on judicial  
review. The rationale given for the holding is they “are not there acting  
within the limits of their expertise”.  
[251] With due respect, it is difficult to see how it can be said that the labour  
Arbitration Board at bar, in making its constitutional ruling which the law  
Page: 87  
empowered it to render, was not acting under the limits of its expertise. It  
was, after all, applying the equality rights guaranteed under s. 15(1) of the  
Charter to a dispute arising out of a collective agreement, to whose  
jurisdiction the law entrusts such disputes because its specialized  
knowledge made it best suited to resolve issues arising from that agreement.  
Apart from the importance of Charter rulings, it is difficult to see why such  
rulings should be subject to a different test on judicial review than are other  
statutory rulings. Indeed, it is submitted that a reading of Douglas College  
suggests that the real reason for dismissing curial deference to Charter  
rulings by non-curial tribunals, and consequential application of the  
correctness test on judicial review, is actually their importance. Even on  
that argument, however, this judgment submits there is no reason not to  
apply the same test of patent unreasonableness under which judicial review  
of other statutory rulings are conducted.  
[252] Be that as it may, it also must obviously be recognized that all the opinion to  
the contrary from this quarter is to no avail in face of definitive ruling from  
the Supreme Court of Canada that the correctness test, and not curial  
deference, must be applied in reviewing Charter rulings by labour  
arbitration boards. Apart from the innate satisfaction that constructive  
critical analysis provides, the utility of the foregoing discussion addressing  
arguments in favour of the correctness standard is academic. Courts are  
bound to apply the correctness standard in broaching Charter rulings of an  
arbitration board at bar. Thus, correctness is the standard against which the  
judge’s endorsation of the Charter ruling by the Arbitration Board that a  
breach of s. 15(1) had been perpetrated by s. 9 of the restraint legislation  
will be addressed. It has to be underscored, however, that in light of the  
RJR-MacDonald case which will next be discussed, the direction to apply  
that standard to Charter rulings must be taken to apply to the breach stage  
of constitutional analyses, inasmuch as that authority instructs that  
deference be observed at the justification stage under s. 1 of the Charter.  
>
the RJR-MacDonald case:  
[253] To briefly recapitulate, as preceding para. 181 points out, the primary  
objective of this discussion on the appropriate judicial review standard of  
arbitral constitutional validity decisions has been to canvass whether the  
constitutional disposition of the Board at bar is reviewable on the  
correctness or patently unreasonable standard. In the course of that  
Page: 88  
discussion, it was explained that the standard for review of arbitral  
applications of ordinary legislation is the deferential patently unreasonable  
one. That standard will be applied when this decision comes to pass upon  
the judge’s ruling vis à vis the Board’s interpretation of s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act. The next issue to be broached under the format for  
treatment of the issues in this appeal as set out in preceding para. 108,  
however, is whether s. 9 infringes s. 15 of the Charter.  
[254] For reasons developed in the preceding discussion, the Arbitration Board’s  
holding that the restraint legislation breached s. 15(1) of the Charter was  
reviewable by the judge on the stringent standard of correctness, and not the  
more deferential one of patent unreasonableness. As explained, there is a  
real logic to applying the latter standard in judicial reviews of arbitral  
findings of Charter violations. Despite the preceding expressed  
reservations, however, binding authority requires this Court must  
accordingly approach assessment of the validity of the complaint that the  
judge erred in finding that s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act infringed  
s. 15(1) of the Charter from the standpoint of whether that holding is  
sustainable on the more stringent standard of correctness.  
[255] The approach to the complaint directed to the holding that the Arbitration  
Board erred in concluding the s. 15(1) breach was unjustifiable under s. 1 of  
the Charter is more complex, however. The judgments filed by the justices  
in RJR-MacDonald Inc. v. Canada (A.G.), [1995] 3 S.C.R. 199, provide  
helpful insight into the standard by which justification analyses under s. 1  
should be conducted and assessed, whilst elaborating upon the role played  
by the established criteria of Oakes to that end. Indeed, RJR-MacDonald  
is an important adjunct to Oakes. The light which RJR-MacDonald sheds  
on the standard of review of the s. 1 justification which will have to be  
addressed in this appeal requires some detailed comment.  
[256] RJR-MacDonald addressed the constitutional validity of federal legislation  
banning all advertising of tobacco products, and requiring health warnings  
to be printed on all packages containing the product. The legislative  
initiative had been challenged both on the ground of Parliament’s power to  
enact it and its compatibility with the Charter. Having rejected contention  
that the legislation was ultra vires Parliament, the Court divided on the  
second constitutional issue questioning whether the measure passed  
Charter muster. All nine justices agreed the ban constituted an  
infringement of the appellate tobacco manufacturers’ rights to freedom of  
Page: 89  
expression guaranteed under s. 2(b) of the Charter. A majority of them  
also agreed the requirement to place the health warnings on the packages  
likewise infringed that freedom. However, the Court narrowly divided on  
the s. 1 analysis. Five held the impugned sections of the legislation were  
not demonstrably justifiable limits on that constitutionally protected  
freedom, whilst the remaining four maintained they were.  
[257] A detailed account of the reasons for the s. 1 division would constitute an  
unnecessary digression from the course of this judgment inasmuch as those  
reasons advert to analyses of the conformity of specific legislation under  
scrutiny in that case with the Oakes criteria for s. 1 applications. However,  
the lead majority and the minority judgments, authored by McLachlin and  
LaForest JJ. respectively, provide particularly germane commentary  
regarding the standard applicable in s. 1 analyses.  
[258] The discussion in RJR-MacDonald of the applicable standard of judicial  
review for such analyses stemmed from inquiry into the burden of proof for  
justification under s. 1 of Charter breaches. As Mr. Justice LaForest  
explained at para. 61 of his judgment, the issue of the burden of proof  
shouldered by the party seeking to justify a Charter violation under s. 1  
arose in RJR-MacDonald from the finding at trial that the civil balance of  
probabilities which the burden imports “must be applied rigorously and the  
evidence must be cogent and persuasive ...”. Holding this view incorrect,  
LaForest J. went on in para. 62 to affirm:  
C
The appropriate “test” to be applied in a s. 1 analysis is that found in  
s. 1 itself, which makes it clear that the court’s role in applying that  
provision is to determine whether an infringement is reasonable and  
can be demonstrably justified in a “free and democratic society”. In  
Oakes, this Court established a set of principles, or guidelines,  
intended to serve as a framework for making this determination.  
However, these guidelines should not be interpreted as a substitute  
for s. 1 itself. It is implicit in the wording of s. 1 that the courts must,  
in every application of that provision, strike a delicate balance  
between individual rights and community needs. Such a balance  
cannot be achieved in the abstract, with reference solely to a  
formalistic “test” uniformly applicable in all circumstances. The s. 1  
inquiry is an unavoidably normative inquiry, requiring the courts to  
take into account both the nature of the infringed right and the  
Page: 90  
specific values and principles upon which the state seeks to justify the  
infringement.  
[259] Immediately before the foregoing commentary, LaForest J. had indicated the  
words in that passage had been prompted by the need to dispel “a  
misconception of this Court’s jurisprudence” held “by some commentators,  
that the proportionality requirements established in Oakes are synonymous  
with, or even superceded, the requirements set forth in s. 1". Immediately  
after it, LaForest J. went on at para. 63 to stress that “the Oakes  
requirements must be applied flexibly” inasmuch as the “word ‘reasonable’  
in s. 1 necessarily imports flexibility”. In this regard, he underscored the  
significance of Dickson C.J.C.’s warning in Oakes “against an overly  
formalistic approach to s. 1 justification” by stating at p. 139 of Oakes that  
“although the nature of the proportionality test will vary depending on the  
circumstances, in each case the courts will be required to balance the  
interests of society with those of individuals and groups”. LaForest J. then  
continues in this vein by noting that Dickson C.J.C. “reaffirmed this  
warning” to avoid rigid and inflexible standards in R. v. Edwards Books  
and Art Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 713 at pp. 768-69, and in R. v. Keegstra,  
[1990] 3 S.C.R. 697 at p. 735.  
[260] Although Mr. Justice LaForest’s judgment in RJR-MacDonald was written  
in dissent, his views on the approach and applicable standard of judicial  
review in conducting s. 1 justification analyses attracted support beyond that  
of his colleagues who concurred in the dissent. While the more widespread  
support was not without reservation, it did extend to LaForest J.’s  
observation that “(t)he appropriate ‘test’ ... in a s. 1 analysis is that found in  
s. 1 itself” (see preceding para. 258), and his emphasis on avoidance of rigid  
and inflexible standards in approaching s. 1 analyses.  
[261] This added support is expressed in the lead majority judgment of McLachlin  
J. in RJR-MacDonald, and inferentially by other justices in their  
concurrences with her disposition in that case. Thus, at the end of para. 126  
of her judgment, after signifying at its outset agreement with LaForest J.’s  
observation that the appropriate test lies within s. 1 itself, McLachlin J.  
wrote:  
C
While sharing LaForest J.’s view that an overtechnical approach to s.  
1 is to be eschewed, I find no conflict between the words of s. 1 and  
the jurisprudence founded upon R. v. Oakes. ... The latter  
complements the former.  
Page: 91  
[262] The reservation in the foregoing passage with Mr. Justice LaForest’s  
approach is with respect to the existence of any conflict between the  
principles, or guidelines, set in Oakes as the criteria for determining if the  
test of “reasonable” justification under s. 1 had been met. As the extract  
from his judgment reproduced in preceding para. 258 recounts, LaForest J.  
affirmed that the Oakes criteria should not be construed “as a substitute” for  
the “specific values and principles” which are to be “found in s. 1 itself”.  
There, he goes on to add, the standard lies in the word “reasonable”, and the  
flexibility that that notion imports in determining whether a Charter breach  
“can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society”.  
McLachlin J. takes issue with any impression that the established Oakes’  
criteria substitutes for the values expressed in s. 1, holding those guidelines  
complement them. That, then, constitutes her reservation respecting her  
colleague’s approach.  
[263] McLachlin J. then conducts a discussion of the consistency of the Oakes  
criteria with s. 1. In the course of this phase of her judgment, while  
agreeing in para. 132 of RJR-MacDonald with LaForest J.’s point that  
“the Oakes test must be applied flexibly, having regard to the factual and  
social context of each case”, she goes on to observe in para. 134:  
C
... nothing in the jurisprudence suggests that the contextual approach  
reduces the obligation on the state to meet the burden of  
demonstrating that the limitation on rights imposed by the law is  
reasonable and justified. Context is essential in determining  
legislative objective and proportionality, but it cannot be carried to  
the extreme of treating the challenged law as a unique socio-  
economic phenomenon of which Parliament is deemed the best judge.  
This would be to undercut the obligation on Parliament to justify  
limitations which it places on Charter rights and would be to  
substitute ad hoc judicial discretion for the reasoned demonstration  
contemplated by the Charter.  
[264] This canvassing of the role of context turned McLachlin J.’s focus on the  
degree of deference which the courts should accord in s. 1 analyses. In the  
course of this part of her judgment she cautioned against both the flexible  
approach in s. 1 applications, as well as the valid advertence to context,  
causing judicial deference to be extended to the “point of accepting  
Parliament’s view simply on the basis that the problem is serious and the  
solution difficult”. To follow such a course, she warns in para. 136:  
Page: 92  
C
... would be to diminish the role of the courts in the constitutional  
process and to weaken the structure of rights upon which our  
constitution and our nation is founded.  
[265] Interestingly, the tenor of the comments quoted in the preceding paragraph  
places a higher significance on the proportionality requirements than upon  
the importance of the infringing measure’s objective, being the two broad  
areas of inquiry for s. 1 scrutiny by Oakes. Thus, the importance of  
objective is downplayed by the assertion that deference should not be  
accorded simply because “the problem is serious and the solution difficult”.  
The paramountcy of the three aspects of proportionality can be seen  
elsewhere in the discussion as well. As such, this feature of the lead  
majority judgment in RJR-MacDonald imports a significant nuance to the  
Oakes’ test.  
[266] Perhaps of more immediate relevance to the present discussion of the  
standard of judicial review of s. 1 analyses, however, is the manner of the  
endorsation of deference in McLachlin J.’s judgment. This comes in her  
summation of her discussion of the degree of deference to be accorded in s.  
1 analyses. Thus in para. 138 she sums up as follows:  
C
... while I agree with La Forest J. that context, deference and a  
flexible and realistic standard of proof are essential aspects of the s. 1  
analysis, these concepts should be used as they have been used by this  
Court in previous cases. They must not be attenuated to the point that  
they relieve the state of the burden the Charter imposes of  
demonstrating that the limits imposed on our constitutional rights and  
freedoms are reasonable and justifiable in a free and democratic  
society.  
[267] It needs be underscored that the deference in s. 1 analyses being spoken of  
in the foregoing excerpt, and by the Court generally in its commentary on  
that topic in RJR-MacDonald, focuses on deference to Parliament, and not  
to the assessment at first instance of whether reasonable justification had  
been established. In that excerpt from her judgment, McLachlin J. is  
warning against pressing parliamentary deference to the extent of undue  
presumption that the legislative and executive branches would not have  
limited “constitutional rights and freedoms” with measures not “reasonable  
and justifiable in a free and democratic society”. She concludes this phase  
of her judgment with comment on the degree of deference which appellate  
courts should accord to findings at first instance in analysing s. 1  
Page: 93  
justifications. At that juncture, she writes in para. 140, “(a)s a general rule,  
courts of appeal decline to interfere with findings of fact by a trial judge  
unless they are unsupported by the evidence or based on clear error”. In  
other words, judicial deference is accorded on appellate review of s. 1  
analyses such as that required to be observed by appellate courts to factual  
findings at trial. She goes on to observe that the degree of deference may be  
greater with respect “to findings based on evidence of a purely factual  
nature” than “where the trial judge has considered social science and other  
policy oriented evidence” (see para. 141).  
[268] It is possible, therefore, to draw instruction from RJR-MacDonald  
regarding the standard of judicial review guiding s. 1 inquiries into whether  
Charter breaches are justifiable. In contrast with the infringement itself  
which is reviewable on a standard of correctness, justification findings must  
be addressed on a deferential standard. Thus, a deferential and flexible  
approach in light of the full contextual setting of the violative measure must  
be accorded to the legislative initiative or executive action that spawned the  
violation. This approach seeps through subsequent appellate proceedings  
addressing the sustainability of s. 1 determinations. As the two preceding  
paragraphs note, the majority in RJR-MacDonald instructs that analyses of  
justifications of Charter infringements, and the sustainability of the  
conclusions of such analyses, are to be conducted on a deferential standard.  
The majority goes on to direct that the degree of deference fluctuates,  
however, depending upon whether the s. 1 analytical conclusions rest on  
“evidence of a purely factual nature”, or on considerations of “social science  
and other policy oriented evidence”.  
[269] In the result, the standard of judicial review applicable to s. 1 analyses  
extractable from RJR-MacDonald is one of deference, the degree of which  
may fluctuate depending on the nature of the evidence produced in proof of  
reasonable demonstrable justification.  
>
dual and hybrid standards:  
[270] The first step in addressing challenges to the constitutional validity and  
meaning of legislation such as this appeal involves was to settle on the  
standard of judicial review. Reflective of the overall complexity of this  
case, that inquiry admits to no quick answer insofar as the standard of the  
legislation’s constitutional validity is concerned. In contrast, a more ready  
appreciation of the legislation’s statutory interpretation standard is  
Page: 94  
discernible from the authorities. Those authorities were discussed in  
preceding paras. 181 to 213 as a prelude to ensuing treatment of the more  
difficult question of the standard of review that the judge was bound to  
apply to the Arbitration Board’s constitutional findings vis à vis the Public  
Sector Restraint Act. Accordingly, when this judgment takes up the  
challenge to the Board’s statutory interpretation of s. 9 of that Act, on the  
basis of the combined authority of the five cases discussed in preceding  
paras. 181 to 213, it will do so on the footing that the judge’s review of the  
meaning ascribed to that statutory provision was required to be conducted  
on the patently unreasonable standard.  
[271] In contrast, when assessing whether the judge’s upholding of the Board’s  
ruling that s. 9 of the restraint legislation breached equality rights  
guaranteed under s. 15(1) of the Charter was sustainable, the standard of  
correctness will be applied. Despite arguments advanced in preceding  
paras. 214 to 252 that the same deferential standard of patent  
unreasonableness applicable to review of other statutory rulings should  
apply to rulings on infringements of Charter rights, it is recognized that the  
impugned upholding of the Board’s finding that a violation had been  
perpetrated by s. 9 of the restraint legislation must be assessed on the  
correctness standard. Thus, there are dual standards of the deference of  
patent unreasonableness and correctness engaged by the two issues that  
directly focus on the import of the restraint legislation.  
[272] As preceding paras. 253 to 269 go on to explain, the standard for  
conducting and reviewing s. 1 analyses is more complex. Judicial review  
must proceed on the footing that “context, deference and a flexible and  
realistic standard of proof are essential aspects of the s. 1 analysis”. Yet, the  
majority in RJR-MacDonald has admonished that deference is not to be  
stretched to the point that infringements are to be rubber stamped as  
justifiable, thereby relieving the state of its burden of demonstrating its  
incursion is reasonable and justifiable in a free and democratic society.  
Moreover, appellate courts should defer to findings of fact at first instance  
unless “they are unsupported by the evidence or based on clear error”. Yet,  
the degree of appellate deference may be less “where the trial judge has  
considered social science and other policy oriented evidence”.  
[273] As will be apparent from the foregoing précis, directions regarding the  
degree of deference in s. 1 analyses do not crystalize in absolute norm. In  
fact, a hybrid standard for s. 1 analyses emerges from those directions.  
Page: 95  
Although deference and flexibility are held up as essential, strains of  
correctness are also detectable in the admonitions not to go too far in  
endorsing legislative infringements of guaranteed Charter rights, and in  
intervening in findings at first instance resting on policy considerations. As  
a result, in the final analysis, it is more difficult to distill from the  
jurisprudence a coherent standard of review for s. 1 analyses, than it is in the  
fixed standards prescribed for reviews of statutory interpretations and  
Charter findings of violations of entrenched rights.  
[274] In the ensuing inquiry into the sustainability of the judge’s holding of error  
in treating the infringement perpetrated by s. 9 of the restraint legislation as  
unjustifiable under s. 1 of the Charter, this judgment will proceed on the  
footing that the deference and flexibility that the judge was required to  
accord to the limit imposed by the restraint legislation on the  
constitutionally protected rights to pay equity conferred under the collective  
agreements was that which would give sway to the limitation if determined  
to be a reasonable limit demonstrably justifiable in free and democratic  
society. This approach complies with the instruction, unanimously  
endorsed in RJR-MacDonald to find the standard for s. 1 justification  
analyses in the wording of s. 1 itself. That provision subjects the  
enforceability of measures infringing the Charter to “such reasonable  
limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and  
democratic society”. The two italicized words are key to an appreciation of  
the deferential standard of the justification of s. 1 analyses. The first  
imports notions of logic, pragmatism and common sense to the enjoyment of  
individual constitutional rights within the society to which the person  
belongs. The second signifies the justifiability must be axiomatic, self-  
evident and reasonable in the contextual setting of that individual within the  
community. In this light, the standard of justification under s. 1 can be seen  
as akin to the patently unreasonable standard of judicial review of decisions  
by administrative tribunals; or, to inquiries into whether factual findings at  
trial are reasonably borne out by the record before appellate courts. By the  
same token, it is not the more rigorous correctness standard, which  
preceding para. 258 notes LaForest J. rejected, that is imported in s. 1's  
wording.  
[275] It is significant, moreover, that no qualification of the justification appears  
in s. 1 beyond the direction to demonstrable reasonableness. In this regard,  
it is important to bear in mind that the justification invoked there is, in  
Page: 96  
reality, essentially to policy choices behind limitations on Charter rights.  
Furthermore, it will be appreciated that s. 1's conferral of this judicial power  
over justification of policy choices was foreign, if not revolutionary, in a  
society where the Separation of Powers Doctrine within a parliamentary  
governmental system has historically been operative. Whilst tempering that  
system by providing the means of individual court challenges to legislative  
enactments, s. 1's standard of unqualified deferral in judicial passings on the  
justifiability of policy reflects an intent to preserve the Doctrine intact by  
assuring no element of correctness, the standard generally governing the  
judiciary’s applications of law, creeps into justifications of policy choices  
under it. In so rationalizing the judicial role in policy justifications, s. 1 can  
be seen as striving to obviate misplaced assumptions by the judiciary of a  
role of ultimate arbitrator of the propriety of public policy. The call by the  
majority in RJR-MacDonald to lesser deference to policy oriented  
evidence is recognized as casting a wrinkle on the foregoing construction of  
s. 1 as importing full deference in analyses of Charter infringements  
justifications. The majority’s position in that regard will receive further  
mention when the s. 1 analysis at bar is engaged. Before arriving at that  
juncture, however, the sustainability of the decision to uphold the  
Arbitration Board’s finding that s. 9 of the restraint legislation breached s.  
15(1) of the Charter must first be addressed.  
÷
the violation of s. 15(1):  
[276] To date everyone charged with decision-making responsibility in the dispute  
at bar has agreed that s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act infringes s.  
15(1) Charter equality rights in its impact upon the Pay Equity Agreement  
incorporated into the collective agreements. The three members of the  
Arbitration Board were unanimous in that regard. As this judgment’s  
account of the decisions by the Board’s members records, the nominees of  
the parties agreed with the Chairperson’s conclusion, referenced in  
preceding para. 27, that the restraint legislation violated s. 15(1) of the  
Charter, and thereby unanimously endorsed the Chairperson’s viewpoint  
that that statute “permits and extends discriminatory practices as between  
males and females” in depriving affected female workers of the benefit of  
comparative pay equity. As preceding paras. 74 and 75 record, the judge  
agreed that there had been a violation of equality rights, whilst reasoning,  
that having addressed “a discriminatory practice” in the Pay Equity  
Page: 97  
Agreement, Government could not resile from its obligations in that regard  
by reneging on payment of “the incremental pay adjustments for 1988-  
1990" without visiting “an adverse economic impact upon a class of  
employees which Government had recognized as the victims of systemic  
gender discrimination”.  
>
the Ferrell case:  
[277] Government’s attack on the prior rejections of its contention that the  
restraint legislation perpetrated a violation of s. 15(1) equality rights is built  
upon the trial and appellate dispositions of a case out of Ontario. It is  
Ferrell v. Ontario (Attorney General) (1997), 149 D.L.R. (4th) 335, (Ont.  
Gen. Div.), aff’d (1998) 168 D.L.R. (4th) 1 (Ont. C.A.). Ferrell addressed  
allegations of breach of employment equality rights guaranteed under s. 15  
of the Charter by repeal of an employment related statute which, as its  
preamble stated, recognized that aboriginal people, disabled people,  
members of racial minorities and women experienced higher rates of  
unemployment in Ontario “caused in part by systemic and intentional  
discrimination in employment”. That statute, as its title the “Employment  
Equity Act, 1993” indicates, moved to repair that inequality by a series of  
measures. It is unnecessary to detail them here. It is suffice to note, as did  
Morden A.C.J.O., who authored the appellate disposition in Ferrell, at p. 6,  
that “the chief target of the statute was systemic discrimination”. Two years  
after passage of the statute, subsequent to a change of government in  
Ontario, it was repealed by an enactment of the Ontario Legislature.  
Members of the groups whom the repealed statute had been designed to  
protect sought to have it declared unconstitutional and of no effect on the  
grounds that it violated their s. 15 equality rights.  
[278] In the trial of the Ferrell case, Dilks J., as p. 338 of the trial report records,  
addressed two issues that are of immediate concern to the sustainability of  
the impugned holding by the judge at bar that a violation of s. 15(1) had  
been perpetrated by the restraint legislation. The first was whether a  
positive duty exists under the equality rights guaranteed by the Charter “to  
enact employment equity education” and, having done so, was there “a  
corresponding duty to leave the same in place”. Secondly, and alternately,  
absent any such positive duty, having enacted the employment equity  
legislation, whether “the Government was bound to leave the legislation in  
place”.  
Page: 98  
[279] As to the first question, Dilks J. concluded at p. 342 that “the overwhelming  
weight of authority negates the existence of any duty under the Charter to  
legislate”. Earlier at p. 340, Dilks J. had stated:  
C
The application of the Charter must be confined to government  
action as opposed to inaction. Given societal systematic  
discrimination, such inequality is not the government’s creation; it is  
a societal problem, one which the government may well address but  
which it is under no obligation under the Charter to do so. As  
Iacobucci J. stated in Symes v. Canada ... “we must take care to  
distinguish between effects which are wholly caused, or are  
contributed to, by an impugned provision, and those societal  
circumstances which exist independently of such a provision.” In  
Andrews McIntyre J. put in this way at p. 186 “to begin with  
discrimination in s. 15(1) is limited to discrimination caused by the  
application or operation of law ...”.  
[280] Having decided there was no positive duty to legislate, Dilks J. also reached  
a negative realization of the second issue. His reason, expressed at p. 343,  
for holding Government was not bound to leave the legislation in place was  
essentially because the repealing legislation had “no substantive effect” and  
thus could not have been “in violation of the Charter”. He viewed the  
Ontario Legislature as “simply” having “restored the situation which existed  
prior to the enactment of the Employment Equity Act 1993". He then  
supported that statement by reference to three Supreme Court cases on  
which comment will presently be made, whilst noting:  
C
Indeed, counsel have been unable to refer me to a decision, at any  
level, in which there was a successful challenge to the constitutional  
validity of the repealing provisions of a statute.  
[281] Morden A.C.J.O. traversed those issues of the constitutional duty to  
legislate and of the obligation to keep in place legislation in addressing the  
appeal from Dilks J.’s decision that no Charter violation had occurred as a  
result of the repeal of the legislative commitment to implement employment  
equity. As to the first issue, having concluded that any duty resting on  
Government to address systemic discrimination relating to employment  
equity had been acquitted through a Human Rights Code that remained on  
Ontario’s statute books, Morden A.C.J.O. saw no need to draw a  
determinative conclusion on whether s. 15(1) of the Charter “imposes a  
positive duty on legislatures to enact legislation to combat systemic  
Page: 99  
discrimination in employment”. Nevertheless, he then went on at p. 118 of  
the appellate judgment in Ferrell to voice his “present view ... that no such  
obligation is imposed”. He then proceeded to discuss relevant authorities  
bearing on that opinion, the large preponderance of which supported his  
viewpoint.  
[282] Morden A.C.J.O. likewise supported Dilks J.’s position on the second issue  
that there was no constitutional duty to keep the repealed legislation in  
place. In reaching this conclusion Morden A.C.J.O. reasoned at p. 16:  
C
If there is no constitutional obligation to enact the 1993 Act in the  
first place I think that it is implicit, as far as the requirements of the  
constitution are concerned, that the legislature is free to return the  
state of the statute book to what it was before the 1993 Act, without  
being obligated to justify the repealing statute under s. 1 of the  
Charter. If this is so, it cannot be said that there is any legislative  
distinction involved as the first step in a s. 15(1) analysis. The effect  
of the repeal is that there is, as was the case before the enactment of  
the 1993 Act, no mandatory affirmative action operating in the area of  
employment. This does not create or involve any distinction or any  
issue of equal protection of the law - and the effect is not a  
distinction. ...  
[283] The upshot of the trial disposition in Ferrell, and its appellate affirmation,  
was general agreement that there is no positive duty on Government to  
address systemic discrimination in employment in the workplace; and, if  
Government elects to legislate in that sphere, it is free to subsequently  
repeal the initiative without the repealing measure being declared an  
impermissible infringement of s. 15(1) equality rights. The rationale of the  
immunity from successful Charter challenge is that the repeal creates no  
distinction attributable to “government action” that denies the “equal  
protection” and “equal benefit” assured under s. 15(1). Instead, Ferrell  
reasons, the discrimination’s source is systemic, not originating from  
“application or operation” of law. Hence, legislatures are “free to return”  
society to its previous state, with the inequity being considered as a  
“societal problem”, not being of “governments creation”. Thus, as the trial  
decision puts it, the repealing legislation is of no constitutional “substantive  
effect”, and is not open to “successful challenge of (its) constitutional  
validity”. In short, Ferrell advances the proposition that relief from  
Page: 100  
systemic discrimination given by a Legislature may be eliminated by that  
same Legislature without constitutional violation of s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
[284] Shortly, the validity of that proposition will be discussed. First, however,  
mention will be made of the role played by Ferrell in the antecedent  
proceedings, and the role which counsel for Government argues this Court  
should ascribe to Ferrell in this appeal.  
>
prior advertence to Ferrell:  
[285] Inasmuch as the three Arbitration Board decisions were delivered some  
several months before the trial judgment was delivered in Ferrell, that case  
played no part in the arbitration proceedings. As preceding para. 27 notes,  
Government’s position that no violation of s. 15(1) of the Charter rested on  
contention that the effect of s. 9 of the restraint legislation was merely to  
substitute one process for another. The chairperson’s rejection of that  
argument was based on the conclusion, which preceding para. 54 explains  
was shared by the other Board members, that s. 9 violated s. 15(1) of the  
Charter because it “disproportionately and adversely affected female  
employees ... by depriving them of the benefit of pay equity in comparison  
with employees in male-dominated job classifications ...”.  
[286] The judge who heard the applications attacking the Board’s award did have  
the benefit of the trial judgment in Ferrell. He did not, however, have the  
benefit of the appellate disposition in that case which was not delivered  
until after the judge handed down the appealed decision at bar.  
[287] Shortly after adopting the remarks of the Board’s chairperson quoted in  
preceding para. 74 that culminated in his observation that s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation “does not seek to remedy inequality”, but rather “to  
curtail and postpone” the agreed “equal pay for female employees”, the  
judge mentioned that Government had enlisted the trial judgment in Ferrell  
in support of its submission that no s. 15(1) Charter breach had been  
perpetrated by s. 9's enactment. The judge went on to mention Government  
had argued that s. 9:  
C
[53] ... is analogous to the repeal legislation considered in Ferrell,  
that is, Section 9 essentially repealed the provision of the Collective  
Agreement requiring the payment of pay equity adjustments for the  
period prior to the date when the adjustments were determined.  
[288] The judge, however, rejected the analogy, stating that s. 9 “did not purport  
to repeal the Pay Equity Adjustment but to vary its implementation”. Thus,  
Page: 101  
as already noted in preceding para. 75, he rejected the Government  
submission of benign constitutional effect of s. 9, whilst affirming the  
Charter breach as a result of s. 9's “adverse economic impact upon ...  
victims of systemic gender discrimination”.  
[289] Hence, advertence was had to the trial disposition in Ferrell, but its  
application to the circumstances at bar was rejected on the ground that the  
impugned legislation in this case did not repeal a governmental  
commitment, but varied it.  
>
Government’s reliance on Ferrell:  
[290] As has already been noted, counsel for Government placed heavy reliance  
on Ferrell to support his position that the restraint legislation did not violate  
s. 15(1) of the Charter. In so doing, this time having the benefit of the  
appellate disposition in Ferrell, he holds up the extract from it, reproduced  
in preceding para. 282, which he describes as the kernel of the Court of  
Appeal disposition in Ferrell. He represents that passage, as well as the  
entire reasoning at trial and appeal in that case, as persuasive authority and  
logic for proceeding on the footing that if a Legislature is under no  
constitutional obligation to pass legislation in the first place, it may exercise  
its power of repeal without judicial intervention on constitutional grounds.  
This really is the gist of Government’s position in its argument that s. 9 of  
the Public Sector Restraint Act did not infringe s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
[291] While the main part of Government’s argument on the Charter breach  
centers on its power to rescind undertakings that it had no constitutional  
obligation to make in the first place through enactment of repealing  
legislation, its submission that no constitutional breach had been perpetrated  
by the restraint statute was not entirely confined to that argument. Thus,  
tacitly conceding that repealing legislation might in some instances violate  
guaranteed Charter rights even when affecting governmental commitments  
undertaken with no obligation to have done so, Government concedes in its  
factum that the repealing statute “must not discriminate between those  
persons or class of persons, the measures are designed to benefit”.  
Expanding on this in oral submissions, Government’s counsel described the  
legislative power of repeal as being complete as long as it was “across the  
board” and does not discriminate.  
[292] Counsel enlists Service Employees International, which has already been  
discussed in preceding paras. 143 to 147 in connection with the  
Page: 102  
jurisdictional issue, as an example where constitutional infringement can be  
perpetrated in legislative repeals of governmental obligations. As earlier  
mentioned, that case involved consideration of legislative elimination of pay  
equity adjustments previously extended to female employees in the public  
sector of Ontario. The Legislature had done this through amending  
legislation that repealed a prior statutory commitment which introduced a  
comparative proxy method for determining compliance with pay equity.  
That method’s elimination resulted in almost all of a union’s public sector  
female workplaces being declared ineligible for pay equity. Only a small  
portion of those workplaces continued to be eligible, whilst the others were  
forced to bear the brunt of Government’s legislative action. In the result,  
O’Leary J. in Service Employees International found the repeal of the  
amending legislation in violation of s. 15(1) of the Charter because it  
perpetrated a discrimination in that it did not apply fairly and equally to all  
within the group.  
[293] Drawing inverse analogy with Service Employees International, counsel  
for Government argues there was no discrimination in the repealing  
legislation at bar inasmuch as it applied fairly and equitable to all in  
postponing implementation of the Pay Equity Agreement. Counsel placed  
particular stress on O’Leary J.’s comments on p. 526 of that case where he  
had indicated, if the Ontario Legislature had simply repealed pay equity,  
rather than just amending the legislation and repealing the proxy  
mechanism, then Ferrell would have been applicable in Service Employees  
International. Insisting the effect of s. 9 of the restraint legislation at bar  
was to impose “a blanket prohibition against retroactive payment” upon “all  
recipients” targeted in the Pay Equity Agreement appended to the Collective  
Agreements “for the same specified time”, Government’s position is that  
“(n)o component of the class receiving the benefit was singled out to be  
treated more or less favourably”. This being the case counsel for  
Government reasons Ferrell, and not Service Employees International  
applies, and the trial judge’s upholding of the Board’s Charter violation  
finding was incorrect.  
[294] It also should be noted that at one juncture in its submissions, Government’s  
factum, to a degree seemingly inconsistent with its heavy reliance on  
Ferrell, acknowledged the judge was correct in observing “that section 9 of  
the Act did not repeal the Pay Equity Agreement, but rather varied its  
implementation”. The excerpt from the judge’s reasoning reproduced in  
Page: 103  
preceding para. 75 supports this reading of the judge’s view of s. 9's effect.  
In also allowing the correctness of the judge’s statement that this had “an  
adverse economic impact” on “the class of employees” subject to gender  
discrimination, Government nonetheless maintains the judge erred in  
concluding this impact “meant that section 9 violated the Charter”. Then  
the factum asserts:  
C
The outright repeal, as opposed to postponement, of pay equity would  
obviously have an adverse economic impact, but is constitutionally  
permissible under the decisions in Ferrell, Dunmore and Service  
Employees.  
[295] Despite this momentary ambivalence regarding the effect of s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation, it is clear nonetheless that Government is contending its  
across the board three year deferment of its obligations under the Pay Equity  
Agreement constituted a repeal of undertakings to address systemic gender  
discriminations that it had no obligation to address in the first place. In  
those circumstances, having blanket non-discriminatory effect, as was held  
in the excerpt reproduced in preceding para. 282 to have been the impact of  
the repealing legislation in Ferrell, Government argues that it is also “free  
to return the state of the statute book to what it was before ... without being  
obligated to justify the repealing statute under s. 1 of the Charter”. This is  
the primary basis for its persistence in insisting that s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act perpetrated no violation of s. 15(1) of the Charter,  
and that the judge was in error in holding otherwise.  
[296] Government’s counsel enlists a policy consideration to further support the  
claim of error in holding that no breach had been perpetrated. He suggests,  
that when governments legislate to counteract systemic discriminatory  
practices if they are not free to return to the situation existing prior to the  
enactment, then they will be reluctant to enter the legislative field in the first  
place. Counsel submits it would be ironic if the Charter’s underlying  
purpose of fostering fuller realization of basic fundamental rights were to be  
hampered or thwarted by judicial interventions that risk governmental  
initiatives aimed at curbing systemic discriminations being held  
unrepealable. He points out that the appellate disposition in Ferrell also  
made reference to that same irony where, at p. 17, Morden A.C.J.O. made  
mention of the “inhibiting effect” on such legislative initiatives if they:  
Page: 104  
C
... once enacted, became frozen into provincial law and susceptible  
only of augmentation and immune from curtailing amendment or  
outright repeal without s. 1 justification.  
[297] Therefore, Government’s persistence in maintaining a breach of s. 15(1) had  
been committed by the restraint legislation’s curtailment of its obligations to  
make pay equity payments during the period of the statutory restraints is  
threefold. Firstly, following Ferrell, it claims freedom to restore the  
situation which existed prior to it entry into the Pay Equity Agreement, or,  
as latter put in Ferrell “to return to the state of the statute book ... without  
being obligated to justify the repealing statute under s. 1 of the Charter”.  
Secondly, while allowing that that general power of repeal without Charter  
consequences could be compromised if the repealing measure fell unfairly  
and inequitably on some, and thereby became a source of further inequality  
as was the case in Service Employees International, Government contends  
such was not the effect of the restraint measure at bar. Finally,  
Government’s counsel raises the policy consideration canvassed in the  
preceding paragraph as reason for legislative scope to modify or curtail  
governmental obligations to make the pay equity payments in the period of  
restraint without the amending or repealing legislation being susceptible to  
review for want of compliance with equality rights guaranteed under s.  
15(1) of the Charter.  
>
NAPE’s response:  
[298] Counsel for NAPE opens her response to Government’s position by  
portraying the impugned restraint legislation provision as having repealative  
effect. It will be recalled, as the excerpt from his decision in preceding  
para. 75 shows, that the judge at one point described the obvious effect of s.  
9 as postponing “the achievement of pay equity”. Moreover, as just pointed  
out in preceding paras. 294 and 295, Government’s counsel, drawing from  
that passage, at one juncture of his argument spoke of s. 9 as not repealing  
the Pay Equity Agreement “but rather varied its implementation”, although  
this was a momentary vacillation from the main theme of his argument  
which was based on the legislation having an across the board repealing  
effect. The position of counsel for NAPE regarding s. 9's effect is  
unambivalent, however. She maintains the monetary effect of s. 9 was not  
just to postpone or vary the promise of pay equity, but was clearly to take  
away forever the entitlement of affected employees to the pay equity  
Page: 105  
adjustments, payable under the Pay Equity Agreement in the three fiscal  
years of restraint.  
[299] While classifying s. 9 as repealing governmental obligation to make three  
years of pay equity adjustments, NAPE’s counsel nonetheless underscores  
the repeal effected at bar is not analogous to the repeal legislation  
considered in Ferrell to which, as preceding para. 287 notes, Government  
likens it. Instead, NAPE submits, it is more akin to the repeal effected in  
Services Employees International inasmuch as it, too, perpetrated it own  
discrimination. The Union’s counsel describes that discrimination as  
stemming from the problem recreated and reanimated by s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act in giving new life to a discriminatory wage practice  
that had been remedied. Counsel dismisses the general immunity, which  
she interprets Government’s argument constructed on Ferrell to essentially  
suggest by observing that all statutes are subject to Charter scrutiny.  
[300] There are two prongs to NAPE’s view of the discriminatory effect of the  
repeal brought about through s. 9 of the restraint legislation. Firstly, its  
counsel submits the repeal failed to take into account the effect it would  
have on a group already disadvantaged economically because they are  
women. Secondly, she points to the plight of employees who retired in the  
interim between incorporation of the Pay Equity Agreement into their  
respective collective agreements and s. 9's enactment. Those retiree’s  
counsel stresses, ceased to work in the expectation that their pensions would  
be adjusted when the financial consultants referred to in preceding para. 8  
had arrived at the quantum of wage adjustment requisite to achieve the  
promised pay equity. Some of these, she maintains, had even taken early  
retirements on the understanding that their pensions would be adjusted. The  
upshot to those retirees was reduced benefits comparable to their former  
colleagues, and this was decried by NAPE’s counsel as both discriminatory  
and a breach of faith.  
[301] The primary gist of NAPE’s insistence that the judge was correct in  
upholding the Arbitration Board’s holding that s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation infringed s. 15(1) of the Charter, therefore, is based on its  
discriminatory effect. Noting that Government’s contrary position  
essentially rested on the contention that no breach could have been  
perpetrated by legislative repeal of commitments conferring benefits such as  
pay equity which it had no obligation to have enacted in the first place,  
NAPE’s counsel at one point in her oral submissions indicated she took no  
Page: 106  
exception generally with that assertion, nor with Ferrell’s endorsation of  
that position. However, she maintains that is not the situation here where  
repeal of the obligation to make pay equity adjustments during the three  
year restraint period constituted discrimination based on sex in violation of  
the equality rights guaranteed under s. 15(1) of the Charter. In sum, then,  
NAPE’s quarrel is not with the general across-the-board power of  
legislative repeal of governmental commitments, but with the discrimination  
that it argues s. 9 perpetrated in the circumstances at bar.  
>
essence of the s. 15(1) ruling:  
[302] The kernel of the judge’s reasoning for upholding the Arbitration Board’s  
unanimous holding that s. 9 of the restraint legislation violated s. 15(1) of  
the Charter is contained in the excerpts which appear in preceding paras.  
74 and 75. As can be seen from them, the judge viewed s. 9 as visiting an  
adverse impact upon employees whom Government “had recognized”  
previously as victims of “systemic gender discrimination”. The judge’s  
casting s. 9's effect as impacting upon Government’s recognition through  
the Pay Equity Agreement of the need to address discrimination brought  
about by the longstanding practice of underpaying women in the public  
sector through the commitment to pay equity is significant. It signifies the  
judge correctly construed the statutory effect of s. 9 as revoking  
Government’s undertaking to make the disputed pay equity adjustments  
which it had recognized in the Pay Equity Agreement as necessary to  
address an important longstanding consequence of systemic gender  
discrimination. From the judge’s perspective, then, the impugned  
legislative measure was directed to revoking a right or privilege by  
curtailing or postponing “entitlement to equal pay for female employees”.  
[303] In essence, then, the judge’s s. 15(1) Charter ruling reflects an appreciation  
that the repealing legislative measure restored gender discrimination in the  
payment of women employed in the public sector. However, the language  
of his reasoning clearly expresses his view that the revived sexism was not  
systemic, and that that type of discrimination had been eliminated through  
the Pay Equity Agreement. It was rather a new inequality created by  
enactment of the restraint legislation. This is a very significant aspect of the  
impugned decision as it underlies the judge’s rejection of the repeal at bar  
being of benign constitutional effect, as was held to be the repeal in Ferrell,  
Page: 107  
with which, as preceding paras. 287-288 recount, Government seeks to  
analogize it.  
[304] In treating s. 9's effect as the repealing of entitlement to pay equity during  
the three year restraint period, the judge actually went right to the heart of  
the s. 15(1) violation issue. It shows he viewed s. 9's operative effect as  
revoking a benefit conferred by Government by executive commitment to  
pay equity. While acknowledging the repeal impacted adversely upon  
“recognized” victims of “systemic gender discrimination”, the judge was not  
suggesting that that systemic inequity was restored. Instead, the legislative  
revocation was seen by the judge as violating s. 15(1) of the Charter by  
depriving employees in female dominated classes of that “equal protection  
and equal benefit of the law without discrimination ... based ... on sex ...”  
over the three year restraint period that had been promised to those  
individuals through the Pay Equity Agreement. Although this resulted in  
those employees being once more covered with a veil of gender  
discrimination, purely from the legal perspective, it was perceived by the  
judge to emanate “under the law”, and thus to have perpetrated a violation  
of the affected employees’ equality rights guaranteed by s. 15(1).  
[305] This perception of s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act as perpetrating a  
discrimination in contravention of s. 15(1) by repealing its commitment to  
pay equity adjustments over the restraint period, rather than as restoring  
“systemic” gender discrimination, lies at the essence of the judge’s s. 15(1)  
infringement ruling. As stated in the adopted excerpt quoted in preceding  
para. 74, “once government entered into the Pay Equity Agreement” it could  
not repeal that commitment “without infringing s. 15(1)”. That statement  
shows the ratio of the infringement ruling to be the judge’s view that  
Government crossed the rubicon in entering the pay equity field in the  
manner it did. Hence, its action in repealing its undertakings in that respect  
during the restraint period could not merely be dismissed as restoring the  
systemic gender discrimination which it had not been obliged to address in  
the first place.  
[306] The judge’s reasoning, then, indicates he viewed s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation as creating its own impermissible inequality by repealing a  
recognized pre-existing discriminatory distinction, and thereby perpetrating  
a new inequality through its own statutory law. His rationale speaks to the  
creation of impermissible inequality through Government action perpetrated  
in s. 9's statutory repeal, and not to restoration of a situation where  
Page: 108  
Government purportedly might absolve itself from constitutional  
repercussion by relying on the immunity from obligation to take action in  
the first place to repair a systemic gender discrimination.  
[307] Discussion will now turn to analysis of the merits of the arguments directed  
by both counsel to the judge’s upholding of the Arbitration Board’s finding  
of s. 9's infringement of the affected employees’ constitutionally protected  
equality rights. Before proceeding directly to the crux of that analysis,  
however, it will be helpful to give contextual setting to it with some  
preliminary observations that arise out of aspects of the preceding  
discussion.  
Page: 109  
>
preliminary commentary:  
[308] There are five preliminary points that need be made before proceeding to  
analyse the core of the s. 15(1) violation ruling.  
[309] The first is to dispel any reservation concerning the repealative effect of s. 9  
of the Public Sector Restraint Act insofar as this appeal’s issue of  
entitlement to the retroactive pay equity adjustments is concerned. In  
preceding paras. 294 and 295, it was noted that at one point in its factum  
Government suggested s. 9 did not effect a repeal, but a variation of the Pay  
Equity Agreement by postponing its commencement to the restraint period’s  
expiry. It is true the judge did speak of postponing the achievement of pay  
equity. Moreover, as preceding para. 179 has already noted, this entire  
discussion of the constitutional issue assumes arguendo that that  
postponement also extinguishes Government’s obligation to respond to its  
undertakings to make pay equity adjustments retroactively on expiry of the  
restraint periods. Subject, then, to that assumption being held sustainable in  
the canvass of its statutory interpretation, it follows that, in its postponing of  
the achievement of pay equity, s. 9 had a repealing effect insofar as this  
appeal’s central issue of entitlement to retroactive pay equity adjustments is  
concerned. On this point, then, agreement is voiced with the portrayal by  
NAPE’s counsel of the restraint legislation as having repealative effect.  
[310] Secondly, at one point in his decision the judge had observed that collective  
agreements to which Government is a party are “law”, whilst citing Douglas  
College at p. 585 as authority for that affirmation. It follows that the Pay  
Equity Agreement, added to the collective agreements which are subject to  
the proceedings at bar, had also to be viewed by him as “law”. In fact, the  
judge specifically stated he was treating that Agreement as such. No  
exception can be taken with that conclusion. Its significance in the present  
context is that it lends reason to the impugned decision’s approach of  
treating s. 9, as wiping out a power conferred by “law” thereby imposing a  
disability visiting afresh gender discrimination, not by restoring the  
eliminated systemic discrimination, but through application and operation of  
the repealing law.  
[311] The third point is that it is unnecessary for the purpose of disposition of the  
challenge to the Charter infringement ruling to come to determinate  
conclusion regarding the submission of NAPE’s counsel that s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation visited discrimination on retirees who ceased to work in  
the period between Government’s promise of pay equity and its enactment  
Page: 110  
of the s. 9 repeal. It should be noted that, in rejoinder to NAPE’s position in  
that respect, which is summarized in preceding para. 300, Government put  
forth three rebuttals generally based on lack of evidence of female  
retirements; the Pay Equity Agreement’s prescribed incremental  
implementation; and any discrimination being a factor of entry into the work  
force rather than s. 9's repealing effect. Beyond stating that neither NAPE’s  
submission regarding the plight of that category of retirees as an upshot of s.  
9, nor Government’s three rebuttals, could be dismissed as specious, but  
each side scores serious points in them, there will be no need to pass on  
their relative merits. This is because, as will presently be seen in the  
analysis of the s. 15(1) violation issue, concentration will center on the first,  
and more general discrimination posited by NAPE’s counsel, viz: the  
repeal’s discriminatory effect on a group already disadvantaged because  
they work within female dominated classes.  
[312] The fourth preliminary observation is to note that the policy consideration,  
canvassed in preceding para. 296, advanced to support Government’s  
challenge of the judge’s upholding the arbitral Charter violation ruling,  
will play no role in the analysis of that challenge. This is because, with all  
due respect, this judgment sees no irony or “inhibiting effect” if repeals of  
legislative initiatives aimed at curing intrusions into protected fundamental  
rights and liberties are subject to constitutional muster. After all, the  
framers of the Charter contemplated that laws infringing such basic  
guaranteed rights and freedoms could be enacted, but might nonetheless be  
enforceable if justifiable under s. 1. This is one of the cardinal  
distinguishing marks between the Canadian and American constitutions. If  
there remains any ground to apprehend inhibitions in passage from inaction  
to governmental action as a result of the potential of such initiatives  
becoming “frozen into provincial law” once enacted, then there is no irony  
to it inasmuch as such an eventuality must have been in contemplation when  
the Charter was proclaimed.  
[313] Fifthly and finally, with respect to the nonexistence of positive duties on  
governments to act to ensure citizens the full measure of their fundamental  
rights guaranteed by the Charter, this judgment accepts the views to that  
effect expressed in both the trial and appellate dispositions in Ferrell.  
Hence, no exception is taken with the view expressed at first instance in  
Ferrell, and already recounted in preceding para. 279, that extant authority  
“negates the existence of any duty under the Charter to legislate”; and, as  
Page: 111  
Dilks J. also put it, that Charter applications “must be confined to  
government action as opposed to inaction”. Neither is issue taken with the  
appellate commentary on the governmental positive duty issue which has  
been summarized in preceding para. 281. Thus, agreement is voiced with  
Morden A.C.J.O.’s opinion, that on “present view ... no such obligation is  
imposed”.  
[314] The central question for analysis, then, is the validity of the premise  
articulated in the passage from Ferrell reproduced in preceding para. 282,  
which asserts, assuming no constitutional obligation to enact, it is implicit  
“that the legislature is free to return the state of the statute book to what it  
was before”. Given that the commitment made in the subsisting Pay Equity  
Agreement is “law”, as was the repealed legislation in Ferrell, inquiry in  
this analysis of the infringement issue will center on whether the reasoning  
in that case, which led to its conclusion that there was no constitutional  
impediment to repealing the legislative commitment, is transposable to the  
pay equity undertaking at bar.  
[315] Hence, when all the underbrush, so to speak, is cleared away, the contextual  
setting of the infringement arm of the constitutional issue more clearly  
emerges. It exposes the turning question for analysis to be whether a repeal  
of a governmental commitment to redress an inequality stemming from  
systemic gender discrimination can be violative of s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
That question will now be addressed.  
>
infringement question’s analysis:  
[316] Government submits that that question should be resolved negatively. As  
the foregoing discussion explains, built upon Ferrell’s trial and appellate  
dispositions, Government’s attack on the judge’s upholding of the arbitral s.  
15(1) violation finding rests on the premise that across-the-board repeals of  
antecedent governmental commitments to redress systemic gender  
discriminations wreak no discrimination through application or operation of  
law, but merely restore societal systemic discrimination that Government  
was not obliged to address in the first place. From that perspective,  
following Ferrell, Government’s counsel stands on the legislative freedom  
to return to the state prior to the commitment to pay equity without  
constitutional repercussions. In that light, s. 9 of the Public Sector  
Restraint Act is perceived as having no substantive effect beyond restoring  
the pre-existing discrimination of systemic societal origin in respect of  
Page: 112  
which there is no constitutional obligation on Government under s. 15(1) to  
take remedial legislative action.  
[317] As the preceding discussion also recounts, NAPE’s counsel challenges that  
stance. She does not, as a general proposition, take issue with the  
legislative power of Government to make blanket across-the-board repeals  
of pay equity commitments without infringing s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
However, she argues such repeals must not leave discriminatory effects in  
their wakes. In the circumstances at bar, she maintains, the restraint  
legislation’s repeal perpetrated a discrimination incompatible with the  
Charter by the new life that it gave through s. 9 to an inequitable wage  
practice that had been remedied by the Pay Equity Agreement. Hence, she  
rejects the notion advanced in Ferrell that repealing provisions of statutes  
have no substantive effect giving scope for constitutional challenges to  
legislative repeals of prior commitments that Government had been under  
no positive duty to make. Thus, whilst apparently agreeing with Ferrell’s  
position that Governments are not bound to leave commitments remedying  
systemic gender discriminations in place, she nonetheless clearly insists  
they must do so with repeals that do not, in themselves, have discriminatory  
effects. In the case at bar, she submits, s. 9 of the restraint legislation had a  
discriminatory impact which breached s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
[318] This judgment agrees that s. 9 had a substantive discriminatory effect, and  
concurs with the judge’s conclusion that the Arbitration Board was correct  
in its unanimous holding that s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act  
infringed equality rights guaranteed under s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
However, that discrimination is not totally akin to that identified in Service  
Employees International with which NAPE’s counsel aligns it. For  
reasons given in preceding para. 311, some hesitancy is felt over equating  
the positions of employees who may have retired in the period between the  
promise and the repeal of pay equity at bar with those of the employees in  
Service Employees International affected by the repeal of the comparative  
proxy method for determining compliance with pay equity. As already  
stated in those reasons, there is no need to canvass the discriminatory effect  
which counsel for NAPE alleges was created for such retirees by s. 9.  
[319] The discrimination grounding this concurrence with the judge’s ruling on  
the s. 15(1) breach issue is rather the first of the two which preceding para.  
300 recounts was mentioned by counsel for NAPE, viz: the discrimination  
perpetrated on all the members of the female dominated classes who were  
Page: 113  
deprived under s. 9 of three years of benefits secured under the Pay Equity  
Agreement, and not just the interim retirees. In identifying the blanket  
effect on all beneficiaries under the Agreement who had already been  
economically disadvantaged because they are women as the s. 15(1)  
Charter discrimination, it is recognized that this analysis comes face-to-  
face with Government’s thesis that across-the-board repeals of measures  
taken to redress systemic gender discriminations are not open to successful  
challenge under s. 15(1) of the Charter. As already indicated, it is accepted  
for the purpose of this analysis that s. 9 effected such a blanket repeal to all  
promisees under the Pay Equity Agreement with respect to their  
entitlements to pay equity over the three year period of statutory restraint.  
However, this judgment respectfully takes issue with the notion, advanced  
in both of Ferrell’s trial and appellate dispositions, and enlisted by  
Government in this appeal in support of its submission of error in the  
finding of the s. 15(1) Charter violation, that governments are not obliged  
to keep in place measures taken to redress prejudicial distinctions so that an  
across-the-board repeal of governmental commitments to remedy systemic  
gender discriminations, such as the pay equity undertaking, has no  
constitutional repercussion providing scope to contend that that repeal  
perpetrated a violation of the Charter’s s. 15(1).  
[320] The reason for rejecting that notion is essential agreement with the judge’s  
adoption of the conclusion expressed in the passage reproduced in  
preceding para. 74 that “once government entered into the Pay Equity  
Agreement to address what it agreed was a discriminatory practice, it could  
not, without infringing s. 15(1) revoke or make unlawful a right or privilege  
that would affect or have an adverse impact on individuals of a particular  
gender”. With due respect, it cannot be said, as the trial decision in Ferrell  
did in the passage from it reproduced in preceding para. 279, that the  
operative effect of the repeal brought about by s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation was to revive “a societal problem” of systemic gender  
discrimination. Neither may it be sustainably argued, by drawing analogy  
with the passage from Ferrell’s appellate judgment, reproduced in  
preceding para. 282, that no “distinction or any issue of equal protection of  
law” is presented by the repeal of the obligation of pay equity during the  
restraint period hiatus because the effect of the repeal is to cause “no  
mandatory affirmative action operating in the area of” pay equity.  
Page: 114  
[321] To the contrary, the very fact that “no mandatory, affirmative action” was  
left operating by the s. 9's repealing effect on the Pay Equity Agreement lies  
at the root of the reason a contravention of s. 15(1) equality rights was  
perpetrated by s. 9 of the restraint legislation. At the time of the enactment  
of that repealing provision, there was no “societal problem” of “systemic  
gender discrimination” insofar as the female dominated classes within the  
public sector covered by the Pay Equity Agreement were concerned. The  
direct effect of the repeal in s. 9 was not to restore systemic discrimination.  
That had been extinguished, so there was no systemic inequity upon which  
s. 9 could operate. The repeal rather operated to extinguish the “equal  
benefit of the law” created through Government’s pay equity commitment  
for the three fiscal years of restraint extending from April 1, 1988, to March  
31, 1991. In so doing it perpetrated its own gender discrimination “under  
the law” in violation of s. 15(1) of the Charter. While it created  
discrimination as a consequence of its abrogation of the pay equity benefits  
for the three year restraint period, s. 9 neither revived nor restored the  
systemic inequity that had been eliminated.  
[322] The discrimination effected by the repeal, then, was the product of the  
Government’s action. It could not be legitimately attributed to a “societal  
problem” when its immediate cause was the legislative repeal’s nullification  
of the commitment to pay equity over the three year period. Although under  
no obligation to have redressed the problem in the first place, once it did so,  
as the judge held, it was not open to Government to revoke its commitment  
without violating s. 15(1). That commitment conferred a right on affected  
employees to the pay equity adjustments, and a concomitant duty on  
Government to provide them. The incorporation of that right into those  
employees’ collective agreements invested their Union with power to  
enforce that right through normal grievance procedures if Government  
reneged in whole or in part on its commitment. Government did renege on  
its promise by its revocation through s. 9's repeal of the right to pay equity  
to which it had committed itself in the Pay Equity Agreement. As the judge  
stated, this had “an adverse impact on individuals of a particular gender”.  
That impact was felt by those employees in the female dominated classes of  
the public service who were entitled to the salary adjustments under the  
Agreement over the restraint period, but were denied them by s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation. That denial, then, was the legislative repeal of the  
commitment through the postponement of the pay equity adjustments, and  
Page: 115  
constituted the infringement of the affected employees’ equality rights  
guaranteed under s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
[323] On the basis of the foregoing analysis, therefore, this judgment rejects  
Government’s contention that negative response should be given to the  
question of the capacity of a repeal of a governmental commitment to  
redress systemic gender discrimination to be violative of s. 15(1) of the  
Charter. Government’s premise of insubstantive restorative effect of the  
restraint legislation does not withstand analysis. While not siding with  
NAPE counsel’s acceptance of neutral s. 15(1) Charter effects by blanket  
across-the-board repeals, this judgment does agree with her contention that  
the s. 9 repeal at bar had violative discriminatory effect, although not on  
affected retirees, as such, but on all members of the affected female  
dominated classes.  
[324] Accordingly, the judge’s upholding of the Arbitration Board’s finding that  
s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act infringes s. 15(1) of the Charter  
must be affirmed, unless there be some binding authority that would  
constrain revisiting that conclusion. The presence of such an eventuality  
will now be explored.  
>
the impact of proffered authorities:  
[325] Ferrell posits three cases in support of its premise that governments are not  
bound to keep in place their actions aimed at eradicating prejudicial  
discriminations, and that outright legislative repeals have no substantive  
effect other than restoring the situations that existed prior to passage of the  
repealed legislative measures. If those cases lend support to that  
perspective of legislative repeals, then the binding effect of them would  
require revisitation of the foregoing conclusion that the judge was right in  
ruling that s. 9's repeal of Government’s commitment to the pay equity  
salary adjustments during the restraint period perpetrated a violation of s.  
15(1) of the Charter. Reference has already been made to these authorities  
in preceding para. 280 where mention was made of intent to discuss them at  
a later stage. That stage has now arrived.  
[326] The three cases are: Symes v. Canada, [1993] 4 S.C.R. 695 at 764-765;  
NWAC v. Canada, [1994] 3 S.C.R. 627 at 633; and, Thibaudeau v.  
Canada, [1995] 2 S.C.R. 627 at 655. Like the case at bar, all three of these  
case, addressed s. 15(1) Charter violations in the context of gender  
discrimination. None of these authorities support the premise of  
Page: 116  
insubstantive restorative effect of legislative repeals, and their consequential  
neutral impact upon s. 15(1) equality rights, however. In the first place,  
none of them dealt with the effect of statutory repeals. Both Symes and  
Thiboudeau addressed the constitutional validity of federal income tax  
legislation that imported no aspect of repeal. NWAC dealt with a claim of  
positive duty on the federal Government to include a native women’s  
association in funding provided to the Canadian Aboriginal community to  
assist its participation in constitutional reform discussions. Thus, NWAC  
dealt with the governmental executive inaction, not the effect of legislative  
repeals.  
[327] Moreover, not only do Symes, Thiboudeau and NWAC not speak to the  
effect of legislative repeals, but neither do Ferrell’s specific references to  
them appear to assist the general thesis of blanket statutory repeals having  
insubstantial restorative effect in their across-the-board vacations of the  
fields which the repealed measures address. The highlighted reference to  
pp.764-765 of Symes has already been quoted within the passage from  
Ferrell reproduced in preceding para. 279. It speaks of the importance of  
distinguishing between legislative effect and societal circumstances  
independent of the statute whose constitutional validity is challenged.  
Likewise p. 655 of the dissenting judgment in Thibourdeau accentuated by  
Ferrell speaks of the importance of distinguishing between the “source” and  
the “perpetration” of the inequality, whilst stating: “(a)lthough s. 15 of the  
Charter does not impose upon governments the obligation to take positive  
actions to remedy the symptoms of systemic inequality, it does require that  
the government not be the source of further inequality”. In similar vein,  
Ferrell’s reference to p. 633 of NWAC shows the Court’s focus in NWAC  
was also on whether governmental action was the source of discriminatory  
inequity in contravention of s. 15(1) of the Charter. This is apparent from  
the statement of issues defined there which included whether Government  
was obliged to provide funding to a native women’s association to represent  
the interests of female Aboriginal persons equal to that it had made  
available to male-dominated Aboriginal groups.  
[328] As it was in this case, therefore, the s. 15(1) Charter scrutiny in Symes,  
Thiboudeau and NWAC was directed to the immediate or proximate  
governmental action effectuating or triggering the gender discrimination,  
rather than to the unfortunate societal circumstances in which such  
prejudices fester. As the foregoing analysis of the infringement issue  
Page: 117  
manifests, focus in this appeal has accordingly converged on Government’s  
enactment of s. 9 of the restraint legislation and the repeal it effected of the  
pay equity commitments as the source of the s. 15(1) prohibited  
discrimination. In view of the reality that the freedom from discrimination  
guaranteed by s. 15(1) is “limited to discrimination caused by the  
application or operation of law” (see preceding para. 279), s. 9 was the  
proper place of concentration, and not the unfortunate penchant of  
humankind that breeds societal systemic discriminations. Therefore, while  
the immediate or proximate action under challenge for its compatibility with  
s. 15(1) of the Charter in the case at bar was s. 9's legislative repeal, the  
impugned governmental actions in the three authorities relied on in Ferrell  
involved no statutory repeals.  
[329] Accordingly, the authorities cited in Ferrell give no reason to retreat from  
the conclusion the judge was correct in holding that once Government acts  
to commit itself to pay equity to address what it agrees was a discriminatory  
practice, it could not revoke its undertaking through legislative repeal  
without infringing s. 15(1) of the Charter. Thus, with due respect, none of  
these cases support Government’s position erected on Ferrell that it was  
free to repeal the commitment without the constitutional repercussion of  
having to justify its action under s. 1 of the Charter. None of those  
authorities involved legislative repeals of commitments given by the  
executive or legislative branches of government. Moreover, whatever  
peripheral support may be drawn from them redounds to support of the  
judge’s upholding of the violation finding, rather than its rejection.  
>
the Churchill Reversion case:  
[330] While no authority has been cited counteracting the conclusion that  
Government’s repeal of its commitment to pay equity through s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation infringed constitutionally guaranteed equality rights,  
neither, as preceding para. 280 notes to have been the case in Ferrell, was  
this Court referred “to a decision, at any level, in which there was a  
successful challenge to the constitutional validity of the repealing  
provisions of a statute”. Nevertheless, this jurisdiction is quite familiar with  
such a successful challenge, although not one mounted within the Charter’s  
context. It came in Re Upper Churchill Water Rights Reversion Act,  
[1984] 1 S.C.R. 297.  
Page: 118  
[331] That case held the statutory repeal of an enactment of this Province’s  
Legislature, authorizing the execution of a lease to exclusive water rights on  
the upper Churchill River for the generation of hydro-electric power, to be  
ultra vires. McIntrye J., who delivered the Court’s unanimous decision,  
reasoned the repealing statute was in pith and substance a colourable  
attempt to impair extra-provincial rights acquired by Hydro-Quebec in a  
power contract signed by the Quebec corporation with the lessee under the  
statutory lease. Having concluded at p. 335 that the repealing statute’s  
purpose was “to interfere with the rights of Hydro-Quebec outside the  
territorial jurisdiction of Newfoundland”, McIntrye J. held in Churchill  
Reversion that the repealing legislation was ultra vires of the House of  
Assembly.  
[332] Albeit in the context of the federation’s distribution of powers, Churchill  
Reversion, therefore, stands as a clear precedent of a successful challenge  
to the constitutional validity of the repealing provisions of a statute. On its  
authority, it must be taken as law that constitutional challenges for want of  
vires may be mounted successfully before courts against outright legislative  
repeals which in pith and substance are seen as colourable attempts to affect  
extra-provincial rights enjoyed outside the territorial jurisdiction of the  
legislating body. Although not decided in the Charter context, Churchill  
Reversion’s holding that the statutory repeal was of no force and effect, and  
its concomitant direction that this Province continued to be bound by the  
statutory lease, counters Ferrell’s thesis, and Government’s contention, that  
legislatures have no duty to leave legislation in place, and have  
untrammelled power “to return the state of the statute book to what it was  
before ...”.  
[333] There appears to be no reason why Churchill Reversion’s precedent of  
successful constitutional challenge of the statutory repeal should not have  
application in the circumstances at bar. If successful challenges can be  
raised to the constitutional validity of a blanket statutory repeal for lack of  
vires under s. 91 or s. 92 of the Constitution, there is no basis to posit that  
such challenges should not likewise be mountable for violations of  
constitutionally protected rights and freedoms guaranteed by the Charter.  
Although, as was the case of its disposition at trial, the appellate judgment  
in Ferrell made no mention of Churchill Reversion, it is reasonable to  
conclude from Ferrell’s adoption of a case supporting its thesis of  
legislatures not being bound to keep legislation redressing systemic gender  
Page: 119  
discriminations in place, that Ferrell would have rejected the foregoing  
analogous extension of Churchill Reversion to its thesis. The referenced  
case is Dunmore v. Ontario (Attorney General) (1997), 37 O.R. (3d) 287  
(Gen. Div.), and the passage quoted from it by Ferrell giving grounds to  
infer it would have rejected the notion of capacity to challenge repeals of  
Charter sensitive laws appears in p. 301 of Dunmore, which is endorsed at  
p. 17 of the appellate judgment in Ferrell. It reads:  
C
... if the Legislature is free to decide whether or not to act in the first  
place, it cannot be the case that once it has acted in a manner that  
enhances or encourages the exercise of a Charter right, it deprives  
itself of the right to change policies and repeal the protective scheme.  
[334] The first thing observable about that statement from Dunmore is that there  
is nothing particularly untoward about legislative bodies in the Canadian  
federation being deprived of legislative powers. Through constitutional  
agreement at the federation’s inception both orders of government limited  
their respective parliamentary sovereignty in the division of powers effected  
in ss. 91 and 92 of the Constitution. This deprived one order from taking  
actions within the jurisdictional powers of the other. Canadian  
jurisprudence is rife with instances where either federal or provincial  
governments were held deprived of power to take impugned actions.  
[335] The second observation about the Dunmore statement is that it must be  
recognized the Canadian orders of government were not stripped of power  
to change or repeal “protective” schemes to which they had committed  
themselves to ensure fuller realization of rights and freedoms guaranteed  
under the Charter. This is because the Charter makes those constitutional  
guarantees explicitly subject to reasonably justifiable limitations prescribed  
by law. Hence, the Charter does not deprive the executive and legislative  
branches of government of the power to act in reasonably justifiable  
violation of constitutionally protected rights and freedoms. The laws and  
actions of those branches are susceptible to scrutiny by the judiciary on  
individual challenge of their Charter compatibility. Offending breaches are  
rendered unenforceable only if the state is unable to establish that they are  
justifiable in a free and democratic society. It is not tenable, then, to  
maintain legislatures have been completely denuded of power to enact  
measures trenching on Charter rights where the incursions are  
demonstrably justifiable under s. 1.  
Page: 120  
[336] While Governments have not deprived themselves of legislative power to  
repeal protective schemes enhancing Charter rights through commitments  
to such benefits as pay equity, which they were free in the first place to  
decide whether or not to provide, it is inarguable that those Governments,  
nonetheless, court risk of so depriving themselves if they are unable to  
demonstrate that the abrogations of the commitments through their repeals  
are demonstrably reasonable and justifiable in a free and democratic society.  
However, the fact that risks of deprivations of power to “repeal the  
protective scheme” designed to enhance enjoyment of Charter rights exist  
does not validate the statement in Dunmore enlisted by Ferrell. This is  
because it certainly is the case that the Legislature intended to court risks of  
being deprived from acting in a manner that trenches upon fundamental  
rights and freedoms. This was an essential purpose behind the engrafting of  
the Charter into the law as part of the “supreme law of Canada”.  
[337] Accordingly, the passage in Dunmore enlisted by Ferrell affords no basis  
to argue the inaptness of the analogy drawn between the repeal in Churchill  
Reversion, and the one effected at bar through s. 9 of the Public Sector  
Restraint Act. It should be noted that Churchill Reversion has fuelled a  
fair amount of comment in academic circles, and raised some quizzical  
brows in the process (see, for example: Newfoundland Resources: The  
Supreme Court Strikes Again, by Professor W.D. Moull (1985) 7 S.C.  
Law Rev. 419 at pp. 429-440; Interpreting the Territorial Limitations on  
the Provinces, by Professor R.E. Sullivan (1985) 7 S.C. Law Rev. 511 at  
pp. 537-545; and The Doctrine of Colourability and Extra-territoriality,  
a case commentary by Professor E. Edinger (1985) 46 Can. Bar Rev. 203 at  
p. 221). However, Churchill Reversion is law and stands as authority for  
the proposition that Legislatures can deprive themselves constitutionally of  
the right to repeal governmental commitments. There would appear no  
ground on which to deny the application of this disability to Charter cases.  
After all, if a legislative repeal can be ruled constitutionally invalid because  
it was aimed at extra-provincial rights outside the territorial jurisdiction of  
Newfoundland and Labrador of a corporation, it would seem to follow  
axiomatically that statutory repeals of commitments to individuals  
enhancing enjoyment of their guaranteed Charter rights should also be  
recognized as capable of successful constitutional challenges, and being  
held unenforceable if unjustifiable under s. 1 of the Charter.  
Page: 121  
Page: 122  
>
upholding of infringement ruling:  
[338] In the result, therefore, there is nothing in the authorities presented in the  
submissions of Government’s counsel that would warrant recanting from the  
conclusion drawn in the foregoing analysis of the Charter infringement  
question. Neither Symes, nor Thiboudeau, nor NWAC support the  
premise that repeals of commitments to Charter values have insubstantial  
restorative effect, nor do they lend sustenance to the related argument that  
across-the-board repeals of such commitments cannot effectuate violations  
of Charter rights. In fact, analogy may be drawn from the authoritative  
precedent in Churchill Reversion supporting the conclusion that the judge  
did not err in holding the Arbitration Board’s finding that s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act infringed s. 15(1) of the Charter.  
[339] Accordingly, the judge was correct in his reasoning set out in preceding  
paras. 74 and 75 that once Government committed itself to pay equity it  
could not repeal that undertaking for the duration of the restraint period as it  
did in s. 9 of the restraint legislation without infringing s. 15(1) of the  
Charter. Government’s contentions that the legislative repeal had no  
constitutional effect, and that it was free to return to the state that existed  
before the commitment through the repealing legislation, cannot be given  
sway. Thus, the judge’s ruling of correctness of the Arbitration Board’s  
unanimous finding of violation of equality rights guaranteed under s. 15(1)  
of the Charter must be upheld.  
[340] Attention will now turn to the final aspect of the constitutional issue. This  
envisages whether the judge erred in holding the Arbitration Board’s  
finding that infringement was not justifiable under s. 1 should be set aside.  
This is the third of the seven issues listed in preceding para. 108. As  
previously explained the second issue challenging the judge’s affirmation of  
the s. 15(1) violation was raised in the Government’s cross-appeal. The  
challenge to the judge’s holding that the violation was saved under s. 1 of  
the Charter, thereby overturning the Arbitration Board’s view to the  
contrary, came from NAPE. That challenge to the judge’s justification  
holding will now be discussed.  
÷
the s. 1 justification:  
[341] As already pointed out in preceding para. 274, and faithful to the instruction  
that the standard of s. 1 analyses is to be found in s. 1 itself, the justifiability  
of the infringement perpetrated by s. 9 of the restraint legislation will  
Page: 123  
proceed on the footing that the law’s requirement of deference and  
flexibility requires assessment of the validity of the judge’s reversal of the  
Arbitration Board’s ruling to be undertaken on the footing of inquiry into  
whether the Board erred in failing to find the perpetrated limitation on the s.  
15(1) equality rights had been demonstrated by Government to be a  
reasonable limit justifiable in a free and democratic society. That analysis  
will also be mindful of the admonition, which, as preceding para. 267 notes  
was conveyed by McLachlin J. in para. 141 of RJR-MacDonald, against  
pressing legislative deference too far, and of its call for lessened degree in  
face of “social science and other policy oriented evidence”. All of this will  
be undertaken in the context of the superimposing Oakes criteria for s. 1  
analyses.  
[342] However, this judgment cannot automatically proceed to apply these criteria  
without some reference to the division in RJR-MacDonald over the degree  
of deference accordable to policy oriented evidence tendered in justification  
of Charter infringements under s. 1. Neither can the s. 1 analysis be  
broached without advertence to the other eye-opening departure of the  
majority from the minority in RJR-MacDonald over the Oakes  
proportionality requirement’s compatibility with justification analyses under  
s. 1. These differences are gleanable from a perusal of the judgment  
summaries in preceding paras. 258 to 269. Both decisions are noteworthy  
for the fuel they provide to frequently voiced criticisms of the judiciary  
which accuse it of actively entering the field of policy-making in its  
Charter applications beyond any tolerable levels sustainable under the  
Separation of Powers Doctrine. Before proceeding to the s. 1 analysis at  
bar, therefore, the call to lesser deference and the questioning of the utility  
of the Oakes proportionality requirement in RJR-MacDonald will first be  
discussed.  
>
the deference difference:  
[343] As already underscored in the earlier discussion of RJR-MacDonald, its  
lead majority and minority judgments unanimously agreed the appropriate  
test in approaching s. 1 analyses is, in LaForest J.’s words, to be “found in s.  
1 itself”. Neither was any exception taken with his interpretation that s. 1  
required a deferential flexible approach by courts in addressing reasonable  
justifications of limits imposed by laws on the enjoyment of guaranteed  
rights and freedoms. However, the majority departed from the minority  
Page: 124  
over the degree of deference. Thus, as already mentioned in preceding para.  
267, the lead majority judgment in RJR-MacDonald, in cautioning against  
pressing parliamentary deference too far, suggested lesser deference should  
be “accorded to ... policy oriented evidence” than to evidence of a “purely  
factual nature”. Inasmuch as s. 1 often centers the justifiability of executive  
and legislative limitations on the enjoyment of Charter rights on the  
reasonableness of policy oriented evidence, it follows that the majority’s  
caution in RJR-MacDonald against overly pressing deference to such  
evidence in justification analyses will frequently be tantamount to a blanket  
call to lesser deference in such inquiries. This would seem to be especially  
so when inquiries turn to consider alternate measures in applying  
components of the proportionality test under s. 1. It also follows that strains  
of correctness, which is the standard normally applicable in judicial  
interpretations of legal effect, will displace the deference to the extent that  
that standard is lessened.  
[344] In contrast, it is apparent from preceding para. 258's account of LaForest  
J.’s judgment in RJR-MacDonald that the majority’s view that a lesser  
degree of deference was called for in s. 1 analyses of justifications of  
limitations upon Charter rights was not shared by the minority. This flows  
from the lead minority judgment’s rejection of the premise that the burden  
shouldered by proponents of justifications of Charter infringements is a  
rigorous one, dischargable upon cogent and persuasive evidence. In other  
words, correctness as the standard of justifications under s. 1 was rejected.  
Instead, the “specific values and principles”, i.e. the policy choices, upon  
which the state seeks to justify limitations on the guaranteed rights’  
enjoyment must be demonstrably justified on the anvil of unqualified  
reasonableness, thereby importing no trace of correctness, but only  
deference, into the standard of s. 1 analyses. Hence, the tenor of LaForest  
J.’s reasoning in the key segment from his judgment summarized in  
preceding para. 258 does not endorse any notion that the wording of s. 1  
calls for the lesser degree of deference that the majority propounded in  
RJR-MacDonald.  
[345] There exists, therefore, a marked distinction between the majority and the  
minority in RJR-MacDonald over the standard of s. 1 analyses. The  
minority viewed it as one of unqualified deference to the policy choices  
behind infringements, whilst the majority construed it as importing a lesser  
degree of deference to them. That difference is not without significance.  
Page: 125  
The judiciary’s adjudicative function is usually discharged on the standard  
of correctness. When deference is required in judicial decision, correctness  
is supplanted by reasonableness. This being the case, the minority’s view of  
unqualified deference leaves no room for correctness in analyses of the  
justifiability under s. 1 of limitations prescribed by law on the enjoyment of  
Charter rights, whilst the majority opens the way for correctness to  
displace deference to the degree of its lesser measure.  
[346] In addressing this difference in RJR-MacDonald, it is essential to advert  
firstly to the underlying purpose of the Charter and s. 1's role in it. In this  
way, the real change wrought by the Charter’s advent, and its  
harmonization with subsisting principles of the Constitution, becomes  
clearer and brings the import of those differences more directly to light.  
The underlying purpose of the Charter was to place in the hands of  
individuals the means to more effectively enforce and enjoy their  
guaranteed fundamental rights and freedoms to the extent that no rational  
objection to the enjoyment of them could be raised in a free and democratic  
society. In subjecting the enjoyment only to reasonable limits demonstrably  
justifiable in such society, s. 1 can be seen as going to the heart of the  
Charter’s purpose.  
[347] In focusing on its purpose, it is important to keep in mind that the Charter  
does not stand alone, in isolation, but is embedded as an integral part of the  
Constitution of Canada. Thus, it is logical to view the Charter as having  
been intended to work its purpose in harmony with subsisting principles of  
the Constitution. Lamer C.J.C. made this point in Cooper where, as  
preceding para. 228 has already noted, he observed that the Charter should  
“not distort the deep structure of the Canadian Constitution”. Amidst this  
“structure”, he went on to affirm, are included the Separation of Powers  
Doctrine and the Parliamentary System of Government, which Lamer C.J.C.  
describes in Cooper as two of the Constitutions “defining features”.  
Shortly afterwards, in Re Provincial Court Judges at para. 138, former  
Chief Justice Lamer portrayed the Doctrine as “a fundamental principle of  
the Canadian Constitution”.  
[348] There is no doubt that the Charter tempered parliamentary supremacy. It  
could not achieve its underlying purpose of endowing individuals with the  
means to immunity from infringements on their basic fundamental rights  
and freedoms without perforce intending to impart commensurate abative  
palliative effect on the operation of parliamentary supremacy within the  
Page: 126  
federation’s orders of government. On the other hand, in endowing the  
judiciary through s. 1 with power to determine the justification of policy  
choices behind executive and legislative actions, the Charter must be taken  
to have intended to rationalize this new judicial commission with the policy  
preserve traditionally reserved to the political branches of government under  
the Separation of Powers Doctrine. This is because no intent can be read  
into s. 1, nor in any other provision of the Charter, to abridge the Doctrine  
by making the judiciary the ultimate arbitrator of the correctness of policy  
decisions by the elected branches of government.  
[349] In accentuating the imperative of rationalizing the judicial power to pass on  
the justifiability of policy choices under s. 1 with the executive and  
legislative power over public policy initiation reserved under the Separation  
of Powers Doctrine, it is fully recognized no claim may legitimately be  
made that judicial decision has traditionally been scrupulously free of any  
element of policy. Indeed, there has always been an element of policy  
making in judicial decisions and the mere fact that courts are drawn into that  
political domain is no phenomenon of the Charter (see: Policy Arguments  
in Judicial Decision by John Bell, 1985, Clarendon Press, at p. 5; and  
Pragmatism and Theory in English Law, by P.S. Atiyah, 1987 Stevens &  
Sons, London, at pp. 110-111). However, the judicial role in policy making  
is generally accepted as being incidental and confined to its traditional  
function under the Separation of Powers Doctrine of construing the effect of  
measures having the force of law in the course of applying them. The  
Doctrine accommodates no role in policy making for the judiciary beyond  
that consequential to passing upon whether executive and legislative  
measures achieved their intended policy through interpretations of their  
scope.  
[350] It also must be conceded that no pretense can be made that the boundary  
demarking tolerable limits of policy making in judicial decision is always  
easily ascertainable in practice. Nor may it be maintained that the  
judiciary’s historical sorties into the policy making field have been  
unaccompanied by controversy. Indeed, recurrently down through the years  
those sorties have given rise to tensions between the political and judicial  
branches that have manifested themselves in charges of untoward ventures  
by courts into the policy domain of the executive and administrative arms of  
government. Part of the polemics over judicial policy making stems from  
the reality that it is not possible to neatly pigeon hole the respective  
Page: 127  
functions reserved to the three branches of government under the Doctrine,  
and part from sheer frustration experienced when the political branches  
learn ex post facto of judicial pronouncements holding that measures taken  
by them did not achieve the policy aims that prompted them.  
[351] It is against this historical backdrop that s. 1's empowerment of the judiciary  
to pass upon justification of policy choices behind executive and legislative  
actions must be viewed. In light of the controversy that has reigned for  
years over judicial incursions into the policy field of the elected branches of  
government, it is inconceivable that the Charter would be framed without  
intent to hold s. 1 justifications of policy choices within tolerable limits  
under the Separation of Powers Doctrine. That intent is confirmed on a  
perusal of s. 1. Nowhere in it, nor anywhere else in the Charter, can  
wording be found indicating the degree of deference in justifications of  
policy choices was intended to be ratcheted downward, thereby importing a  
corresponding degree of correctness into the standard. To the contrary, an  
eschewing of any element of correctness can be detected from the  
unqualified preference imported as the adjudicative standard of  
justifications under s. 1. In the result, s. 1 of the Charter is harmonized  
with the Separation of Powers Doctrine by foreclosing the potential for the  
judiciary to assume the role of final arbitrator of the correctness of policy  
initiatives within the purview of the political branches of government.  
[352] Finally, it should be underscored that it is of cardinal importance to so read  
s. 1 in consonance with that other fundamental principle of the Constitution.  
As previously observed in another judgment of this Court, at para. 373 of  
Newfoundland Assn. of Provincial Court Judges v. Newfoundland  
(2000), 191 D.L.R. (4th) 225, that Doctrine is no dry and dusty political  
theory whose utility is confined to interesting academic discussion. It  
emerged from bloody revolutions in the 17th and 18th centuries which  
wrestled from monarchial control power over public policy, and particularly  
access to the pockets of the citizenry, as western nations passed from  
autocratic regimes to democratic statehood. The lessons of history  
accentuate the perils of re-vesting ultimate decisions over policy in  
institutions controlled by persons without elective mandates to make such  
decisions. It is safe to assume the Charter would have been framed in full  
alertness to this peril, and without any intent to distort or disrupt the deeply  
ingrained structural Separation of Powers.  
Page: 128  
[353] Accordingly, it is fundamentally important to keep in mind in adjudications  
involving rights guaranteed by the Charter that its underlying purpose was  
intended to be achieved without throwing out of kilter the established  
separation of powers reserved to the three branches of government under the  
Doctrine. This is why RJR-MacDonald’s endorsement of lesser deference,  
which opens potential for a concomitant degree of correctness into the  
standard of s. 1, is an eye-opener. It appears reasonable to regard any  
element of correctness as inimical to the “defining feature” of the  
Constitution which the Separation of Powers Doctrine embodies; and, as  
neither intended by, nor construable from the wording of s. 1 of the  
Charter. Even more surprising, however, is the division of RJR-  
MacDonald over the compatibility of certain elements of the  
proportionality requirements prescribed in Oakes with justification analyses  
under s. 1.  
>
the division over Oakes:  
[354] The difference between the majority and the minority in RJR-MacDonald  
over the utility of the Oakes criteria is stark. As preceding para. 259 notes,  
the lead minority judgment of LaForest J. in RJR-MacDonald had  
described as “misconception” the notion that the Oakes “proportionality  
requirements ... are synonymous with, or even superceded the requirements  
set forth in s. 1", before it went on to assert that “those guidelines should not  
be interpreted as a substitute for s. 1 itself”. This viewpoint contrasts  
sharply with the lead majority judgment in which, as ensuing para. 261 of  
this judgment records, McLachlin J. found “no conflict” in “the  
jurisprudence founded upon R. v. Oakes” and “the words of s. 1", but rather  
construed that wording as complementing Oakes.  
[355] There was, therefore, clear and explicit disagreement in RJR-MacDonald  
over the relevancy of the Oakes proportionality requirements to s. 1's  
standard for justifying incursions upon guaranteed Charter rights. In view  
of the general acceptance of the utility of those requirements in s. 1  
justification analyses, that division can only be regarded as startling.  
Nevertheless, there is a logic to LaForest J.’s thesis that the proportionality  
requirements articulated in Oakes lack synonymy with the standard for  
justifications implicit in the wording of s. 1 of the Charter.  
[356] In addressing the logic of the minority’s questioning of the compatibility of  
the Oakes criteria as guidelines in applying s. 1, it must first be noted there  
Page: 129  
was no division in RJR-MacDonald over the relevancy of inquiry into  
whether the limit’s objective was sufficiently important to have justified  
overriding the constitutionally protected right or freedom. It is also  
noteworthy that LaForest J.’s suggestion of conflict between the Oakes  
guidelines and the wording of s. 1 centers on the requirements set down by  
that authority for satisfying the proportionality criteria, i.e. the rational  
connection of the limiting measures with the objective behind the limitation;  
the minimal impairment of the guaranteed right or freedom by these  
measures; and, the proportionality between the deleterious and salutary  
effects of the measures taken to achieve the limitation and of the policy that  
spawned it. The lead minority in RJR-MacDonald judgment should not  
necessarily be read as questioning the utility of inquiry into proportionality  
per se. It appears to have focused rather on the relevancy of the aspects of  
that broad criterion which Oakes prescribed as required areas of inquiry  
into its satisfaction.  
[357] Indeed, no exception to considering proportionality as a criterion in  
analysing the justifiability of limitations on Charter rights and freedoms  
would appear tenable. After all, the justifiability of a right’s limitation  
measure will necessarily entail consideration of its proportionality to the  
importance of the communal needs whose objective prompted the limitation.  
However, there appear to be grounds, nonetheless, to support LaForest J.’s  
assertion that the three aspects of proportionality set down in Oakes as  
required avenues of inquiry in s. 1 analyses are not synonymous with the  
justification standard construable in the wording of s. 1. This is because it  
is difficult to perceive how inquiry into the satisfaction of the Oakes  
proportionality requirements can be undertaken without frequently  
transcending the legitimate bounds of judicial policy-making, and thereby  
falling into disharmony with the Separation of Powers Doctrine.  
[358] This difficulty is especially pronounced in applications of the minimal  
impairment requirement. As Iacobucci J. puts it in para. 186 of his  
judgment in RJR-MacDonald, the minimal impairment aspect of the Oakes  
proportionality criterion requires courts “to consider whether the legislature  
turned its mind to alternative and less rights-impairing means to promote the  
legislative goal in question”. This is consistent with Oakes where,  
underscoring the need for justifications under s. 1 to be established on “(a)  
very high degree of probability”, Dickson C.J.C. wrote at p. 138:  
Page: 130  
C
(a) court will also need to know what alternative measures for  
implementing the objective were available to the legislators when  
they made their decisions.  
Hence, the judiciary is mandated by Oakes to determine if the objective of the  
limitation measure could have been realized in a manner trenching less intrusively  
on the affected constitutionally protected right. This inevitably requires courts to  
satisfy themselves not only as to the reasons why the executive or legislature made  
the policy choices behind the limitations whose justification are subject to  
analyses, but also to pass upon the reasonableness of those choices in relation to  
alternatives.  
[359] No linguistic curtain drawn around the minimal impairment requirement can  
mask the reality that in so inquiring into the alternate means of promoting  
legislative or executive goals, the judiciary enters the policy field in a  
manner which defies rationalization with the Separation of Powers Doctrine.  
Such inquiries could hardly be viewed as sorties into the policy arena  
incidental to judicial interpretation of the scope of measures limiting  
enjoyment of Charter rights. These inquiries require the judiciary to  
conduct retroactive assessments of which policy alternatives should have  
been adopted, from amongst the range of constitutional choices permissible  
under s. 1 of the Charter, to achieve the goal of favouring communal needs  
over individual rights in the circumstances obtaining. In that light, it is  
difficult to perceive how these inquiries could be viewed otherwise than ex  
post facto incursions into the field of public policy to an intolerably  
disharmonious degree vis à vis the Doctrine, and thereby distorting that  
defining feature of the Constitution in a manner unintended by s. 1 and  
incompatible with coherent applications of the Charter.  
[360] Stronger cases for greater compatibility with the Separation of Powers  
Doctrine can be made for the two other Oakes proportionality requirements.  
However, even in these instances, there appears to be room for legitimate  
concerns over untoward incursions into the public policy field. That said,  
the relevancy of the rational connection requisite in s. 1 justification  
analyses cannot be gainsaid. Inquiries into the necessity of the rights  
limitation measure, and how well it is tailored to suit the objective of the  
rights’ infringement, are incontrovertibly material to considerations of such  
a measure’s justifiability. Thus, the relevancy of the measure being  
“carefully designed to achieve the objective in question ... not ... arbitrary,  
Page: 131  
unfair or based on irrational considerations”, as Dickson C.J.C. described  
the rational connection component of the proportionality criterion at p. 139  
of Oakes, cannot be denied. To the extent that this proportionality requisite  
engages consideration of the rational connection of the limiting measure  
under s. 1 scrutiny as opposed to an alternate measure which might have  
been adopted in the circumstances obtaining, however, there is room to  
regard the judiciary as transcending its legitimate bounds of policy making.  
[361] Likewise, the materiality, again in Dickson C.J.C.’s words in p. 139 of  
Oakes, of “proportionality between the effects of the measures which are  
responsible for limiting the Charter right or freedom, and the objective  
which has been identified as of ‘sufficient importance’” may not be  
discounted. In fact, analysis of the limitation’s deleterious effect compared  
with its salutary impact in realizing the objective or policy which prompted  
so limiting such rights or freedoms may be seen as lying at the core of the  
delicate balance that s. 1 requires courts to strike between individual rights  
and communal needs. Nevertheless, just as the rational connection provides  
potential for untoward incursions into the policy field, albeit to a lesser  
degree than the minimal impairment requisite, so too does the proportionate  
effect requisite present similar potential. This is essentially because  
inquiries into such effect do not occur in a vacuum, but must entail  
advertence to other potential policy choices to varying degrees depending  
on the circumstances obtaining.  
[362] It is, therefore, because of the scope which the Oakes proportionality  
requirements leave to venture into public policy that this judgment sees  
reason in the minority position in RJR-MacDonald holding it  
misconception to regard them as synonymous with s. 1. It is no answer to  
maintain, as some do, that a policy role was cast on the judiciary by the  
Charter. A perusal of s. 1 within which the standard of its application is to  
be found dispels any such contention. It is true that s. 1 effectively invests it  
with responsibility to pass upon the justifiability of policy choices behind  
Charter infringements. However, that power is exercisable in the context  
of judicial deference to the other branches of government, and in harmony  
with the Separation of Powers Doctrine. This being so, although extending  
the judicial power beyond the traditional role of policy-making incidental to  
judicial interpretations in adjudications of justifications of the  
reasonableness of limitations on Charter rights, it cannot be said that s. 1  
endows the judiciary with licence to stand in the shoes of the other branches  
Page: 132  
of government as ultimate arbitrator of which policy choices were in the  
best interests of the governed. For the foregoing reasons, it would appear  
that the Oakes proportionality requirements court such a risk. Accordingly,  
it seems that some revisitation of them is in order.  
[363] In light of the general acceptance of these requisites as the framework of s.  
1 analyses, it is fully recognized that this judgment is swimming against a  
strong tide of legal precedent in suggesting they be revisited. Yet s. 1 not  
only must be construed as constraining courts to strike a delicate balance  
between individual rights and societal needs, but also as exacting an equally  
sensitive balance between the more contemporary constitutional feature of  
justifications of Charter infringements imported in s. 1, and the long-  
established constitutional hallmark that the Separation of Powers Doctrine  
represents. This second balance requires harmonization of s. 1's  
justification of policy choices behind Charter infringements with the role  
of the elected branches of government in policy formation. For the  
foregoing reasons, the Oakes proportionality requirements provide potential  
for incursions by the judiciary into the field of public policy transcending  
the bounds of judicial sorties into that field which are tolerable under the  
Separation of Powers Doctrine, and go beyond s. 1's intent in empowering  
the judiciary to pass on the justification of Charter infringements. Hence,  
there is a need to revisit those requisites.  
[364] It is recognized it does not lie with this Court to conduct such revisitation.  
Nevertheless, whilst not downplaying the relevancy of importance and  
proportionality as criteria in s. 1 analyses, it is submitted that an essential  
component frequently missing in applications of s. 1 is the rationalization of  
this relatively new power to address the justifiability of power choices  
behind Charter infringements with the Separation of Powers Doctrine. The  
importance in Charter applications of melding harmoniously this newest  
defining feature of the Constitution with that longer established one has  
already been underscored in this judgment. The lessons of history support  
the imperative of the blend. While it would overly dramatize the  
importance to democratic society of advertence to the Separation of Powers  
to hold up the spectre of the bloodshed in which the Doctrine evolved, it is  
no histrionic foresight to draw real potential for heightening unease over  
undue incursions by the judiciary into the policy domain of the elected  
branches of government, going beyond those contemplated by s. 1  
justifications in unintended disharmony and conflict with the Doctrine.  
Page: 133  
[365] The seeds of this potential are already evident in the unease that has  
frequently been expressed over undue incursions into the public policy field  
in Charter applications. Despite protestations to the contrary, it has to be  
acknowledged there is an air of legitimacy to many of these complaints.  
This judgment argues they can be addressed by taking a fresh look, not at  
proportionality as a criterion per se, but at the proportionality requirements  
laid down in Oakes, whilst lending particular emphasis in so doing on  
harmonizing those requisites with the recognized policy preserve of the  
elected branches of government long entrenched in the Constitution through  
the Separation of Powers Doctrine. There is a need, then, to revisit those  
three gateways to proportionality, and if not to completely reframe them, at  
least to oil their hinges to assure they swing in harmony with the Separation  
of Powers. The judicial power to justify policy choices was intended under  
the wording of s. 1 to be so rationalized with that policy preserve of the  
political branches of government.  
[366] In siding with the minority view in RJR-MacDonald that the  
proportionality requisites laid down in Oakes are not synonymous with the  
requirements set forth in s. 1 for justifications of infringements of  
constitutionally guaranteed rights, this judgment stresses the need for more  
precise definition of the limits of judicial incursions into the public policy  
field in applications of s. 1. Failure to do so will only fuel the ongoing  
debate over untoward incursions into the formation of public policy by  
those with no mandate to do so. The unease which such impressions  
generate can be anticipated not only to undermine confidence in the  
operation of the institutions of government, but also to obscure the  
Charter’s benefit of arming individuals with an effective means of  
enforcing their basic fundamental rights and freedoms to the extent that no  
rational objection can be raised to enjoyment of them.  
[367] While the primary argument for revisitation centers on the need for the  
Oakes proportionality requirements to be rationalized with the policy  
preserve reserved to the elected arms of government under the Separation of  
Powers Doctrine, this is not the exclusive reason to retake stock of their  
utility. There are others. For example, in the wake of the threat to North  
American society so forceability brought to public awareness this past year,  
it would appear timely to vet those requisites with a view to more precisely  
defining the legitimate boundary between individual rights and the state’s  
capacity to adopt preventative investigative practices directed towards  
Page: 134  
societal protection. Likewise, it would seem useful to revisit the entire  
jurisprudence dealing with the proportionality criterion for inquiry into  
whether the standard of reasonable justification laid down in the wording of  
s. 1 might not suffer from the same exhaustive exposition leading to undue  
convolution of that norm to which some contend the conceptual reasonable  
doubt standard of criminal culpability has been exposed.  
[368] Having argued for revisitation of the Oakes proportionality requirements,  
and questioned the call in RJR-MacDonald to lesser deference to policy  
oriented evidence, in each case primarily for lack of congruity with the  
Separation of Powers Doctrine, analysis of the s. 1 phase of the challenge to  
the enforceability of s. 9 of the restraint legislation at bar must, nonetheless,  
proceed on the footing of the directions issued in those two authorities.  
Before proceeding to this analysis, it would appear helpful to briefly  
recapitulate the approach which will be taken to it.  
>
recapitulation of approach:  
[369] The ensuing inquiry into the sustainability of the judge’s ruling that the  
infringement at bar was justifiable under s. 1 will be influenced by four  
considerations that come out of the foregoing discussions. Firstly, regard  
will be had to the wording of s. 1 for the standard on which the inquiry is to  
be approached. As para. 274 of this judgment indicates, and based on the  
discussion in the paragraphs immediately preceding it, the wording of s. 1 is  
construable as setting reasonableness as the standard of justifiability of  
Charter infringements. Hence, attention will focus on whether the  
limitation prescribed by s. 9 of the impugned restraint legislation had been  
proven to be sufficiently reasonable to be held demonstrably justifiable in a  
free and democratic society, as the judge held it was in overruling the  
contrary opinion of the Arbitration Board.  
[370] Secondly, in addressing whether the judge’s holding, contrary to the  
Board’s view, that there was adequate proof to meet that standard, the  
sustainability of his holding will be approached by extending, as the  
majority in RJR-MacDonald instruct, despite misgivings earlier expressed  
over doing so, lesser deference to “policy oriented evidence” than normally  
extendable to “purely factual evidence”. Inasmuch as justifiability of a  
limitation’s enforceability hinges upon the reasonableness of the policy  
choices that prompted the action impairing the constitutionally protected  
Page: 135  
right, this call to lesser deference, as was earlier observed, imports that  
standard into the entire analysis of justification.  
[371] Thirdly, the framework for addressing whether the standard of reasonable  
justification of the infringement perpetrated by s. 9 of the Public Sector  
Restraint Act had been met, as the decision under appeal holds it to be, will  
be the criteria set down in Oakes for conducting s. 1 analyses. This will  
include the proportionality requirements enunciated by that injury. As is the  
case with the direction to lesser deference, notwithstanding reservations  
expressed regarding those requisites, it is recognized that until changed or  
modified they are authoritative and must be followed.  
[372] In following these requisites, and as the fourth and final consideration, the  
ensuing s. 1 analysis will address, at the end of each stage of the appraisal of  
compliance with the Oakes criteria for justifications under s. 1, whether the  
exercise of the judicial power in coming to those findings was in  
consonance with the Separation of Powers Doctrine. It is submitted that the  
addition of this added consideration to the s. 1 analysis finds support in  
Lamer C.J.C.’s affirmation in Cooper, already highlighted in preceding  
paras. 228 and 347, that the Charter should “not distort the deep structure  
of the Canadian Constitution”, amongst which the Separation of Powers  
Doctrine has been numbered since the federation’s inception. Although  
Lamer C.J.C.’s judgment in that case centered on his appeal to his  
colleagues to revisit the power of administrative tribunals to declare laws  
unenforceable under s. 52 of the Constitution Act, his caution against  
distorting the Doctrine in Charter cases affords support for treating the  
instruction that s. 1 is to be applied harmoniously with the Doctrine as a  
valid legal percept.  
[373] Accordingly, directed by these four considerations, this judgment now turns  
to address whether the decision under appeal erred in holding the violation  
of s. 15(1) of the Charter was saved under s. 1 of the Charter, and in  
overturning the majority decision of the Arbitration Board that it was not so  
saved.  
>
sufficiency of objective’s importance:  
[374] The record of proceedings to date evinces unanimous holdings that the  
objective of the restraint legislation was sufficiently important to justify its  
limitation upon the enjoyment by affected employees of their s. 15(1)  
equality rights through the restrictions it imposed in s. 9 upon payments of  
Page: 136  
the promised pay equity. Thus, as preceding paras. 44 and 46 recount, both  
union and employer nominees concurred with the Board chairperson’s  
conclusion, recapitulated in preceding para. 29, that the “pressing and  
substantial objective of saving money” in order “to reduce an escalating  
deficit ... where the financial health and well-being of the Province was at  
stake”, met the first of the criteria laid down in Oakes. Subsequently, as  
preceding para. 77 notes, the judge sided with this unanimous ruling whilst  
reasoning that in light of the “severe fiscal circumstances” being faced by  
Government “the objective of reducing expenditures was sufficiently  
important to justify a limitation on the s. 15(1) Charter rights”.  
>
NAPE’s argument:  
[375] Counsel for NAPE takes issue with the judge’s affirmation of the Board’s  
ruling that the Oakes criterion of sufficient importance had been satisfied in  
the circumstances of this case. She insists the goal of “saving money ... to  
reduce escalating expenses” and the “severe fiscal circumstances”, which  
the judge subsequently held adequate to endorse the Board’s ruling of  
fulfillment of the first of the Oakes criteria, was not a sufficiently  
substantial and pressing objective promoting the values and principles of a  
free and democratic society to support a holding of importance, sufficient to  
override the legislative limit upon the guaranteed equality rights of affected  
employees through the restrictions imposed upon the pay equity promises.  
Stressing the importance of s. 15(1)’s equality rights guarantee in free and  
democratic societies, whilst allowing the possibility that fiscal restraints  
may promote the values and principles of such societies, NAPE’s counsel  
submits courts must still look to the objective behind the rights’ incursions  
which are sought to be justified.  
[376] In so looking to the objective of a right’s limitation, counsel for NAPE  
argues heed must be had to Schachter v. Canada, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 679 and  
to Lamer C.J.C.’s observation at p. 709 that it is settled law that “budgetary  
considerations cannot be used to justify a violation under s. 1”. Viewing the  
“saving of money” in response to “severe fiscal circumstances” as being just  
that, i.e. a budgetary consideration, she argued in her oral submissions that  
the purpose of s. 9 of the impugned restraint legislation “is just about  
money”. Accordingly, counsel maintains it cannot be considered a  
sufficiently important objective to justify s. 9's violation.  
Page: 137  
>
Government’s response:  
[377] In his response to the foregoing reasoning, counsel for Government argues  
that the judge’s holding that the “severe fiscal circumstances” rendered “the  
objective of reducing expenditures” sufficiently important to justify the s.  
15(1) limitation was unassailable. He maintains the judge’s conclusion is  
wholly consistent with the Supreme Court’s assertion in M. v. H., [1999] 2  
S.C.R. 3, where at pp. 72-73 Iacobucci J., who with Cory J. jointly authored  
the majority judgment, held:  
C
It may be that a violation of s. 15(1) can be justified because,  
although not designed to promote equality, it is designed to promote  
other values and principles of a free and democratic society.  
[378] Government’s counsel contends opposing counsel’s submission overlooks  
that the budgetary considerations prompting the sound fiscal management  
which led to imposition of the restraints on the promised pay equity were  
not an end in themselves, but a means to “promote other values and  
principles of a free and democratic society” through the provision of  
appropriate education, health care, social programs and other similar  
objectives which the Charter promotes. In other words, counsel denies it is  
“just about money”, as NAPE claims. He insists regard must be had, as  
NAPE’s counsel in her argument agrees it must, to the objective behind the  
restraints which limited enjoyment of the employees’ equality rights  
protected under s. 15(1) of the Charter. It can be seen from this argument  
that counsel is placing significance on context in this s. 1 analyses, as did  
McLachlin J. in RJR-MacDonald. As to NAPE’s reliance on Schachter,  
counsel counters with PSAC v. Canada, [1987] 1 S.C.R. 424, in which  
Dickson C.J.C. found at pp. 439-440 that restraint legislation whose purpose  
was the reduction of inflation was of sufficient importance to justify  
overriding a Charter right or freedom.  
>
balancing of relative importance:  
[379] The first comment that must be made in broaching the respective merits of  
these arguments is that agreement has to be voiced with NAPE’s counsel  
where she underscores the importance of the s. 15(1) equality rights  
guarantee. However, while indisputably important, as Oakes points out at  
p. 136, these rights are not absolute, but are subject to limitations “where  
their exercise would be inimical to the realization of collective goals of  
fundamental importance”. Iacobucci J.’s suggestion, in the excerpt from his  
Page: 138  
judgment from M. v. H. highlighted in preceding para. 377, that s. 15(1)  
violations might be justifiable if “designed to promote other values and  
principles of a free and democratic society” can be seen to jibe with the  
foregoing statement from Oakes.  
[380] Both of the foregoing assertions, in Oakes and M. v. H. speak to that  
“delicate balance between individual rights and community needs” which,  
as preceding para. 258 records, LaForest J. in RJR-MacDonald construed  
the wording of s. 1 to require courts to strike in considering justifications of  
Charter infringements. Moreover, it would appear that the tension in that  
“delicate balance” is regulated by the word “inimical” employed by Oakes  
at p. 136 of that authority. The inimicalness can be taken to signify that the  
exercise of the individual right must be markedly adverse to the realization  
of the “collective” goal or objective of the “community need”, the  
enjoyment of which would require supplanting the “inimical” limitation on  
the fundamental right or freedom. The use of that key word signals that  
societal goals or objectives may not be trifling ones causing individual  
rights to be displaced by every budgetary need. It must, in M. v. H.’s  
words, be “designed to promote other values and principles of a free and  
democratic society”.  
[381] In this light, it can be said that the process of analysing whether the Oakes  
criterion of sufficient importance to warrant overriding a constitutionally  
protected right has been met is one of balancing the relative import of  
enjoyment of individual rights against the realization of communal needs.  
This “delicate” balance, as LaForest J. describes it, is struck by placing on  
one side of the scale the measure conferring the Charter right. In this case  
that measure is the promise of pay equity addressing the systemic  
discrimination in the workplace. Alongside, on the other pan of the scale, is  
placed the measure limiting the right’s enjoyment together with the policy  
choice that prompted the limitation. In the case at bar that countering  
weight is the repealative effect of s. 9 of the restraint legislation and the  
objective of its enactment. Then, reasoned analysis is conducted by the  
court of the relative importance of the individual, as opposed to the societal  
interest with a view to determining whether the proponent of the latter’s  
paramountcy has established it outweighs the individual enjoyment of the  
affected Charter right. The scale is set at the lesser deference standard to  
policy choices behind the rights’ limitations in compliance with instruction  
to that effect issued by the majority in RJR-MacDonald. If the importance  
Page: 139  
of the societal imperative is assessed to outweigh the individual right, the  
infringement is justifiable.  
[382] Before proceeding directly to apply this analytical justification process to  
the circumstances at bar, four cases will be canvassed bearing on NAPE  
counsel’s insistence that since s. 9 of the restraint legislation is “just about  
money”, falling within the rubric of a budgetary consideration, it cannot be  
used to justify the equality rights’ infringements that it perpetrates. The  
cases constitute the authority upon which she relies in advancing that  
contention, together with three others with which Schachter must be read.  
Following commentary on each case, a synthesis of the legal principles  
extractable from them will be undertaken immediately before the s. 1  
analysis. Then, this phase of the appeal will apply the foregoing process to  
the circumstances of this appeal.  
>
the Schachter case:  
[383] Schachter does not assist NAPE’s rebuttal of the evidence submitted by  
Government in support of justification of the infringement perpetrated by s.  
9 of the restraint legislation. In the first place, Lamer C.J.C., the author of  
the majority judgment, decried at the outset of his analysis at p. 695 of  
Schachter “the state in which this case came to us” in that “the appellants  
chose to concede a s. 15 violation and to appeal only on the issue of  
remedy”. Hence, the Court was precluded “from examining the s. 15 issue  
on its merits”. Consequently, the Court in Schachter was primarily  
occupied with the issue of reading in or severance as a remedy under s. 52  
of the Constitution Act, 1982, for a Charter breach conceded not to have  
survived s. 1,the concession of which attracted an expression of  
dissatisfaction from the Court.  
[384] It is true that in the course of Lamer C.J.C’s judgment he stated that  
violations of the Charter may not be overridden simply for budgetary  
considerations in periods of economic restraint. This assertion, which, as  
mentioned earlier, NAPE’s counsel enlists, was made at p. 709 of  
Schachter. The full context in which this statement occurs reads as  
follows:  
C
Even where extension by reading in can be used to further the  
legislative objective through the very means the legislature has  
chosen, to do so may, in some cases, involve an intrusion into  
budgetary decisions which cannot be supported. This Court has held,  
Page: 140  
and rightly so, that budgetary considerations cannot be used to justify  
a violation under s. 1. However, such considerations are clearly  
relevant once a violation which does not survive s. 1 has been  
established, s. 52 is determined to have been engaged and the Court  
turns its attention to what action should be taken thereunder.  
[385] Although the comments in the foregoing passage were made in a case which  
focused on the appropriate remedy for a Charter breach, and not on  
whether the violation was saved under s. 1, the statement that “budgetary  
considerations cannot be used to justify a violation under s. 1", must be  
received as a statement of law. At the same time, however, the import of  
that assertion by Lamer C.J.C. in Schachter must be gleaned from the  
context in which it appears in that passage. As can be observed, it appears  
in a setting whose primary concentration is intrusion into legislative  
budgetary powers through the remedy of “reading in”. Thus, the comment  
that budgetary factors cannot be used in justifications of infringements may  
be seen to have been made in the context of the sentence following it which  
states these factors become relevant at the juncture when courts come to  
turn their attention to the appropriate remedies for unjustifiable breaches.  
There was no need, therefore, for Lamer C.J.C. to have gone further into any  
discussion of objectives behind budgetary decisions and their relevance to s.  
1 justifications of Charter violations in his judgment in Schachter. By the  
same token, the full context of the passage nonetheless witnesses Lamer  
C.J.C.’s alertness to the distinction, albeit in the context of his pre-  
occupation in that passage with the remedy for unjustifiable Charter  
breaches, between “legislative objective” and “the very means the  
legislature has chosen” to achieve its end through “budgetary  
considerations”.  
[386] In addition to its contextual setting, the statement rejecting the use of  
budgetary considerations in justification of Charter violations must be  
viewed in the context of other authorities, the following three of which are  
particularly germane to the weight which may be placed on budgetary  
measures in s. 1 analyses.  
>
the McKinney case:  
[387] The first of these authorities is McKinney v. University of Guelph, [1990]  
3 S.C.R. 229. In his treatment of the Oakes test of sufficiently important  
objective, the judge whose decision is here under appeal quoted from La  
Page: 141  
Forest J. who had stated at p. 280 of McKinney that the starting point of a s.  
1 inquiry “is an assessment of the objectives of the law to determine  
whether they are sufficiently important to warrant the limitation of the  
constitutional right”.  
[388] The direction to focus from the start on the “objectives” is significant in the  
present circumstances because it supports Government counsel’s point that  
concentration should be placed on the ends, and not the means of an  
impugned limitation. Hence, concentration focuses on the objective of the  
budgetary measure, rather than the need of fiscal saving which is the means  
of achieving that objective. McKinney, then, signals it is the importance of  
the social concern behind the budgetary initiative that is to be taken into  
balance against the infringement of the individual right or freedom.  
>
the M.v. H. case:  
[389] The second case is M.v.H.. Its significance in this appeal’s context lies in  
its instruction, already referenced in preceding para. 377, that budgetary  
needs translating into burdens on the public purse must be linkable to  
objectives “designed to promote other values and principles of a free and  
democratic society” in order to justify s. 15(1) violations. Government’s  
counsel fittingly enlists that instruction to make his point that s. 1  
justifications focus on the ends, and not the means, such as budgetary  
initiatives, employed to achieve objectives in overrides of Charter  
violations. He also correctly interprets the instruction as signifying that  
objectives promoting education, health and like social programs which are  
consistent with values underlying the Charter are eligible considerations to  
be weighed when considering whether limitations on Charter rights and  
freedoms are justifiable under s. 1. This is apparent from the contextual  
setting of the direction, both within the paragraph in which it appears and  
those immediately preceding it.  
[390] Against the background of its context, that directive in M. v. H. will be seen  
as given by Mr. Justice Iacobucci in reaction to a colleague’s approach to  
the latter’s s. 1 justification analysis of the s. 15(1) equality rights violation  
in that case. He described his colleague’s approach as “unnecessarily  
narrow” where the latter had posited that the overriding legislative measure  
“must be respectful of the equality of status and opportunity of all persons.”  
While agreeing that the override’s objective “must be consistent with the  
principles underlying the Charter” in order to meet the first criterion set  
Page: 142  
down by Oakes of sufficient importance, Iacobucci J. observed in para. 106  
of his judgment in M. v. H. that in its full context consistency encompasses  
objectives promoting “both social justice and the dignity of individuals.”  
Indeed, Iacobucci J. went on to observe in the ensuing paragraph of his  
judgment that such objectives had been identified at p. 136 of Oakes as  
values underlying a free and democratic society.  
[391] As already intimated, therefore, the relevance of M. v. H. to this phase of  
the s. 1 analysis is twofold. Firstly, it lends substance to Government’s  
contention that s. 1 justifications turn on the end rather than the means to  
achieve overriding objectives. Secondly, it also furnishes authority for  
counsel’s assertion that such social justice goals as education, health and  
other social programs can constitute pressing and substantial objectives of  
sufficient importance to override Charter infringements. These concerns  
are those “other values and principles of a free and democratic society” to  
which the highlighted instruction in M. v. H. refers. It is those “other  
values and principles” that shape those “collective goals of fundamental  
importance” which Dickson C.J.C., at p. 136 of Oakes, described as having  
been given paramountcy through s. 1 of the Charter over enjoyment of  
individual rights whose exercise would be “inimical” to the realization of  
those goals.  
[392] This notion of paramountcy lies at the very essence of s. 1. It effectuates  
over-all Charter policy by assuring its guarantees of protected rights and  
freedoms are not absolute. Through that paramountcy, the Charter can be  
seen to be speaking, and giving effect, to the classic ideal that liberty in a  
free and democratic society involves individual rights being exercised up to  
the point where they stop short of interfering with the enjoyment of the  
rights of others. However, befitting the supremacy accorded to those basic  
fundamental individual rights and freedoms enforceable under the Charter,  
those “collective goals of fundamental principles” must be of sufficient  
importance to justify limiting the individual prerogatives. Thus, just as the  
enjoyment of individual Charter rights is not absolute, neither is the  
realization of collective communal goals. Oakes has construed s. 1 as  
confining such realization to the goals having sufficiently pressing and  
substantial objectives to override the individual right or freedom.  
[393] The Charter leaves determinations of sufficiency to the courts. M. v. H.  
instructs that considerations of importance are not necessarily restricted to  
reciprocal collective goals of precisely the same nature as the affected  
Page: 143  
individual right whose limitation is sought to be justified. While such  
comparisons may be possible in some circumstances, it is difficult to  
perceive how individual equality rights guaranteed under s. 15(1) can be  
notionally weighed against collective equality rights. This is essentially  
because such rights as perceived individually cannot be conceptually  
considered to operate in jural opposition with any collective abstraction of  
them. The greater the respect of individual equality rights, the more  
extensive is the collective enjoyment of them. Hence, from individual and  
collective perspectives equality rights must be considered in correlative  
jural relationship, and not in opposition which would admit weighing one  
against the other in that “delicate balance” which s. 1 requires courts to  
strike.  
[394] Accordingly, while it may well be feasible to weigh infringements of s.  
15(1) violations against collective objectives directly related to other  
constitutionally protected rights, M. v. H. instructs that the  
counterbalancing collective objective in s. 1 analyses can be “other values  
and principles” as long as they are consistent with the Charter. In holding  
them to such consistency, the instruction tacitly recognizes the Charter  
does not concern itself with trifles. Its entrenchment as an integral part of  
the Supreme Law of Canada bespeaks the order of the Charter’s  
importance, and that of the guarantee of the fundamental rights and  
freedoms enforceable under it. It follows that measures of sufficient  
importance to justify limitations upon those rights and freedoms should be  
directed to objectives consistent with the Charter’s values and principles,  
which are of demonstrably higher imperative than the affected individual  
prerogatives.  
>
the PSAC case:  
[395] PSAC involves circumstances similar to those at bar. In issue in that case  
was the constitutional validity of a budgetary measure effected through  
legislation imposing restraints on public sector compensation enacted in  
pursuance of federal government policy to combat spiralling inflation. The  
Public Service Alliance of Canada sought a declaration that the restraint  
legislation was of no force and effect for want of compliance with s. 2(d) of  
the Charter guaranteeing freedom of association. Being unsuccessful in  
the trial and appellate divisions of the Federal Court, the Alliance pursued  
its quest for the declaration in the Supreme Court of Canada.  
Page: 144  
[396] Finding neither Charter violation, nor other basis to grant the declaration,  
the majority dismissed the appeal. It, therefore, had no need to inquire into  
justification under s. 1. Dissenting in part, Dickson C.J.C. was of the  
opinion that an infringement of the freedom of association guarantee had  
been perpetrated by the restraint legislation, but concurred with the appeal’s  
dismissal on the basis that the violation was justifiable under s. 1. Wilson J.  
dissented, being of the view that the s. 2(d) violation was not justifiable.  
[397] It was Dickson C.J.C.’s treatment of justification in PSAC upon which  
Government’s counsel relies to counter the enlistment of Schachter by  
NAPE’s counsel to support her argument that fiscal savings cannot be used  
in s. 1 justifications of Charter violations. In his rejoinder to that  
argument, counsel for Government responds with the following commentary  
by Dickson C.J.C. at p. 440 of PSAC:  
C
... in Re Anti-Inflation Act, ... a majority of this Court was not  
prepared to conclude that Parliament was wrong in considering the  
inflationary experience of the early 1970's to amount to a situation of  
economic crisis imperilling the well-being of the people of Canada as  
a whole and requiring Parliament’s stern intervention ....  
Accordingly, the Anti-Inflation Act ... was held to be valid pursuant to  
the federal government’s peace, order and good government power.  
The seriousness of inflation underlined by the Court’s decision in Re  
Anti-Inflation Act supports the characterization of Parliament’s  
objective in the present case as relating to a “pressing and substantial  
concern”. I am of the opinion, therefore, that the objective of  
reducing inflation was, at the time of passage of the Act, an objective  
of sufficient importance for the purpose of s. 1 of the Charter.  
[398] As Government’s counsel bills it, the foregoing commentary is a  
consideration quite apropos in weighing the merits of NAPE’s contention,  
which its counsel erects on Schachter, that fiscal saving is not an objective  
“designed to promote other values and principles of a free and democratic  
society” which, as preceding para. 377 has already recorded, M. v. H. posits  
as a basis of s.1 justifications. The pertinence of those words of Dickson  
C.J.C. in PSAC is not diminished because PSAC antedated Schachter by  
some five years. Neither is it affected because the opinion that the  
sufficiency of the importance of the legislative object of reducing inflation  
was reached in a judgment relying on another case that antedated the  
Charter, and considered the importance of curbing inflationary pressures  
Page: 145  
from the perspective that they had become a serious enough national  
concern to warrant invoking the federal legislative peace, order and good  
government power in the Constitution. If economic restraint were  
sufficiently important to warrant the exercise of the federal emergency  
power to enact the restraint legislation in those circumstances, it appears  
quite reasonable for Dickson C.J.C. to have concluded that a subsequent  
restraint measure taken to address other serious concerns over inflation “was  
an objective of sufficient importance for the purpose of s. 1 of the Charter”.  
[399] The immediate relevance to the appeal at bar of the former Chief Justice’s  
commentary in PSAC lies in that conclusion that budgetary restraints  
imposed with the objective of reducing serious inflationary pressures was of  
sufficient importance to justify under s. 1 a Charter violation. By  
analogous extension, this provides firm support for proceeding on the  
footing that mushrooming fiscal deficits urgently requiring containment and  
reduction through budgetary means are sufficiency substantial and pressing  
to justify Charter violations under s. 1. It is the kindred threat to economic  
well-being and security within the affected jurisdiction that justifies  
restraint legislation whose objective is to curtail pressing and substantial  
threats, whether from inflationary pressures or uncontrollable soaring  
deficits. Hence, if Dickson C.J.C.’s opinion that the objective of reducing  
inflation can be “an objective of sufficient importance for the purpose of s. 1  
of the Charter” is a tenable conclusion, then the objective of containing and  
reducing seriously mushrooming unforecasted fiscal deficits must warrant  
similar appraisal.  
[400] Counsel for NAPE downplays opposing counsel’s reliance on the foregoing  
commentary in PSAC by pointing out that it was expressed by Dickson  
C.J.C. in partial dissent. It is true that his judgment in PSAC departed from  
the majority. Be that as it may, the opinion of the architect of the Oakes’  
general principles under which s. 1 inquiries are to be conducted, and the  
roles that Dickson C.J.C. had played in cases leading up to his judgment in  
Oakes, namely: Law Society of Upper Canada v. Skapinker, [1984] 1  
S.C.R. 357; Hunter v. Southam Inc., [1984] 2 S.C.R. 145; Singh v.  
Minister of Employment and Immigration, [1985] 1 S.C.R. 177; and, R.  
v. Big M Drug Mart Ltd., give ample reason to lend weight to his  
commentary in P.S.A.C.. Moreover, there is nothing in the majority  
judgments in PSAC, whose conclusions that no infringement had transpired  
obviated any need to consider s. 1's application, which takes exception with  
Page: 146  
Dickson C.J.C.’s opinion. While Wilson J. dissented from the opinion that  
the infringement as found by Dickson C.J.C. survived s. 1 analysis, she did  
so on the footing that the restraint measures were not rationally connected to  
the objective, and not on the sufficiency of the objective’s importance.  
There being no authority detracting from the rationality of it, there is, with  
due respect to counsel’s contrary view, good reason to treat Dickson  
C.J.C.’s commentary in PSAC as highly persuasive, if not authoritively  
binding.  
[401] Accordingly, PSAC makes a very germane contribution to the present  
discussion on the use of budgetary considerations in addressing s. 1  
justifications of Charter violations. Drawable by analogy from it is  
conclusion that the objective of containing and reducing fiscal deficits  
seriously threatening economic security and well-being by means of  
budgetary measures is an end of sufficient importance for the purpose of the  
Charter.  
[402] Having now completed discussion of these four cases bearing upon  
counsel’s insistence that s. 9 of the restraint legislation, being a budgetary  
measure of fiscal saving, cannot be used to justify the equality rights’  
infringements perpetrated by it, an overview of these cases will now be  
conducted. The purpose of this is to show how those cases, including  
Schachter, meld to provide cohesive a principle on which will be conducted  
the sufficiently importance phase of the s. 1 analysis of the Charter  
violation at bar.  
>
overview of authorities:  
[403] Schachter is not at odds with McKinney, M. v. H. and P.S.A.C. All four  
cases combine and synthesize into one coherent directive guiding  
applications of s. 1.  
[404] Depiction of the assertion in Schachter as foreclosing any consideration of  
budgetary decisions in s. 1 analyses is, with respect, an incomplete  
portrayal. It is true that budgetary considerations alone may not be cited as  
justification for Charter infringements so as to open the way to Charter  
limitations for every budgetary need. A look beyond those needs to the  
objectives of the laws limiting Charter rights, as McKinney directs, is  
required. As already pointed out, the distinction between the budgetary  
means and the objectives which they promote can be seen to have been  
Page: 147  
recognized in the highlighted commentary from Lamer C.J.C.’s judgment in  
Schachter.  
[405] M. v. H. further develops the jurisprudence relating to the sufficiency of  
importance of objectives prompting Charter limitations by re-affirming that  
concentration must be had on objectives, whilst stating that a limitation on  
the enjoyment of equality rights may be justifiable, if, “although not  
designed to promote equality, it is designed to promote other values and  
principles” of a free and democratic society. As has already been noted,  
these “other values and principles” can embrace educational, health and  
other social goals.  
[406] Although handed down before any of the other three authorities, Dickson  
C.J.C.’s judgment in PSAC contains within it direction from which may be  
extrapolated by analogy a principle for conducting inquiries into whether  
fiscal restraints limiting Charter rights and freedoms are sufficiently  
important to be justifiable under s. 1. As preceding para. 401 intimates, that  
principle allows for the budgetary restraint measures to be deemed  
sufficiently important if their objectives are aimed at containing and  
reducing fiscal deficits which seriously threaten economic security and  
well-being within the jurisdiction to which the restraints apply.  
[407] It can be seen that that principle cohesively synthesizes the essential  
ingredients of s. 1 analyses articulated in Schachter, McKinney and M. v.  
H. which have just been highlighted in the foregoing discussion of them.  
Thus, the extrapolated principle does not use budgetary considerations per  
se to justify s. 1 violations, but centers its focus on the objective of the fiscal  
restraint measures, and thereby combines the instructions in both Schachter  
and McKinney. By the same token, in stipulating the curbing of fiscal  
deficits of pressing and substantial concern qualifies as a sufficiently  
important objective to justify infringements, the principle also blends within  
it M. v. H.’s instruction that limiting objectives under s. 1 include those  
“designed to promote other values and principles” consistent with the  
Charter. The latter meld is more indirect, but nonetheless evident. It stems  
from the twin reality that objectives promoting education, health and other  
social programs fall within “other values and principles” consistent with the  
Charter and, if a fiscal deficit of serious enough proportions to threaten  
economic security and well-being has been established to be looming, then  
it can be assumed that those “other values and principles” are  
commensurately threatened as well.  
Page: 148  
[408] Actually, it seems eminently preferable that the affect of fiscal deficits, or  
other economic exigencies, on those “other values and principles”, of which  
M. v. H. speaks, be so left to the indirect proof. This is because by leaving  
the impact of deficits on those “other values and principles” to be inferred  
from the seriousness of such financial shortfalls, specific inquiries into the  
extent of the effect upon educational, health and other essential social  
problems are avoided. This, in turn, has the salutary result of steering the  
judiciary from micro-managing budgets which, it is safe to say, is a power  
with which the Charter had absolutely no intention to endow the courts.  
[409] Having averted to how the principle extrapolated from PSAC embodies an  
amalgam of the directions on the conduct of s. 1 analyses enunciated in all  
four highlighted authorities, attention will now turn to applying it in the  
circumstances at bar. Accordingly, this judgment will now explore whether  
Government has proven that the objective of containing and reducing the  
fiscal deficit which the Province was facing through enactment of the pay  
equity restraints was sufficiently important to justify the override of affected  
employees’ equality rights in s. 9 of the restraint legislation.  
>
sufficiently importance analysis:  
[410] Counsel for NAPE argues the evidence presented by Government did not  
establish the sufficiency of the impugned restraint measure’s importance,  
and the judge therefore erred in upholding the Arbitration Board’s finding  
of sufficiency. She maintains the evidence called by Government on the  
pressing and substantial nature of the economic threat was not nearly as  
extensive as that which she contends a perusal of PSAC will reveal was  
called in that case. Counsel attacks the strength of Government’s evidence  
led in support of the sufficiency of the restraint legislation’s importance on  
two fronts.  
[411] The first questions the credentials of one of Government’s principal  
witnesses who testified before the Arbitration Board regarding the  
seriousness of the fiscal deficit on which Government was attempting to  
justify the restraint legislation’s Charter violation. In this submission,  
NAPE’s counsel points to the transcript of that public servant’s evidence  
before the Board which records him to have been attached to the  
Department of Career Development as Assistant Deputy Minister of Finance  
and Administration at the time of enactment of the impugned restraint  
legislation. Not having been directly associated with Treasury Board or the  
Page: 149  
Department of Finance at the time of passage of the restraint legislation,  
counsel argues that witness’s evidence regarding the seriousness of the  
deficit and the importance of the legislation’s objective in curbing it should  
be discounted. With respect, however, this submission cannot be given  
sway. The witness in question had spent most of his career in Treasury  
Board, and, during the first ten years preceding his tenure as Assistant  
Deputy Minister in the other Department, had been involved in virtually  
every division in it. Moreover, he had returned to Treasury Board in 1993.  
There is, therefore, no basis to seriously question his competency to provide  
the evidence to which he attested before the Arbitration Board.  
[412] The second prong of counsel’s attack is directed towards other evidence  
placed before the Arbitration Board which provides an account of the policy  
reasons behind Government’s decision to impose the restraints which  
affected its pay equity promise, and perpetrated the violation of the s. 15(1)  
equality rights. This evidence was in the form of the Hansard of the  
Minister of Finance’s remarks on his introduction in the House of Assembly  
of the Bill containing the impugned restraint measure. Inasmuch as the  
Minister of Finance is the cabinet minister whose portfolio is most directly  
responsible for governmental fiscal policy, his explanation of the  
background behind the impugned measure’s adoption is obviously highly  
relevant to any assessment of the justifiability of its importance.  
[413] Counsel’s challenge of the Ministers evidence is directed to its  
admissibility. As the agreed list of issues detailed in preceding para. 108  
records, the Arbitration Board’s reference to Hansard is being pursued as a  
separate consideration in this appeal. Accepting its admissibility for the  
purpose of the present discussion, and subject to its confirmation when this  
judgment comes to deal with this aspect of the challenge to the Minister’s  
evidence, it has to be said that the record of his introduction of the  
impugned legislation affords compelling evidence of the sufficiency of the  
importance of Government’s equality rights infringement through its repeal  
of its pay equity promise over the three year restraint period. The following  
resumé affords a flavour of the weight of that evidence.  
[414] The Hansard of March 19, 1991, records the Minister of Finance as  
summarizing the events leading up to the Bill’s introduction. He recounted  
how shortly after passage of its previous budget, Government learned that  
forecasted revenues from the federal Government were to be “somewhat  
reduced”. By late summer or early fall, it had become obvious that a  
Page: 150  
combination of reducing provincial revenues and increased expenditures  
was going to transform a projected $10 million surplus into a $120 million  
deficit. At that time, restraint action was taken through executive initiatives  
to attempt to curb the degree of deficitary escalation. Notwithstanding that  
action, the Minister informed the Assembly, it was apparent a deficit in the  
vicinity of $200 million must be forecasted “if we were to continue the same  
way”, i.e. to provide the same level of services and programmes, in the  
upcoming fiscal year. He forecasted even greater deficits in the order of  
$400 to $600 million for ensuing years just to maintain the same levels of  
governmental services and programmes. In light of these facts, it would  
appear difficult to refute the Minister’s styling of the seriousness of the  
problem posed by these projections of soaring deficits as “horrendous”.  
Neither could exception very well be taken with the portrayal of the  
situation by counsel for Government as “catastrophic”.  
[415] In explaining Government’s policy choice of targeting pay equity in its  
partial response to these deficitary woes, the Minister is recorded in  
Hansard to have pointed out that a “retroactive bill” for pay equity had been  
accruing which, in Government’s estimation, “was in the vicinity of $24  
million”. In this regard, it will be recalled from the account at the outset of  
this judgment of the circumstances of this appeal that the Government had  
been awaiting a report from financial consultants before it would be in a  
position to respond to its promise to make the promised wage equity  
adjustments. Coincidentally, as preceding para. 8 points out, it was not until  
the day after the Minister introduced the restraint legislation, i.e. not until  
March 20, 1991, that that report was finished. It was not received until July  
21, 1991. This explains why Government would not be in a position to  
respond to its undertaking to make the wage adjustment payments until the  
1991-92 fiscal year when a deficit in the vicinity of $200 million was  
forecasted if Government “were to continue the same way”. The Minister’s  
remarks captured in Hansard indicated, then, that relief from the burden of  
that “retroactive bill” would address approximately $24 million of that  
deficit.  
[416] It is against this backdrop that the relative importance of enjoyment during  
the restraint periods of the pay equity promises, endowing affected public  
sector employees with enforceable s. 15(1) equality rights and freedoms  
from systemic discriminations, must be weighed against the policy objective  
behind the violation of those rights and freedoms imposed under s. 9 of the  
Page: 151  
impugned restraint legislation. In light of the foregoing outline of the  
evidence adduced at the arbitration hearing, the scale of relative importance  
can be reasonably seen to be weighted in favour of according paramountcy  
to the limitation which s. 9 effects on the conferred individual equality  
rights for the duration of the restraint period. The sheer magnitude of the  
severe financial situation presented by the prospect of burgeoning fiscal  
deficits that hovered over the Province early in 1991 leads compellingly to  
the conclusion that the implementation of those pay equity promises during  
the restraint periods would, in Oakes’ words already quoted in preceding  
para. 379, be “inimical to the realization of the collective goals of  
fundamental importance”, viz: the reduction and containment of fiscal  
deficits which presented urgent, pressing and substantial threats to the  
Province’s economic security and well-being. As already noted, PSAC  
provides authoritative support for holding that the curbing of such deficitary  
situations, given the threat they invariably pose to those “other values and  
principles” consistent with the Charter which M. v. H. mentions, are to be  
treated as objectives of sufficient importance for the purpose of s. 1  
justification analyses.  
[417] The foregoing portrayal of the enjoyment of the pay equity adjustments as  
inimical in the circumstances obtaining should not be taken as denigrating  
from the importance of the violated equality rights. Neither should there be  
inferred from that characterization any insensitivity to NAPE’s  
understandable frustration, conveyed by its counsel in her submissions in  
this appeal, over Government’s parrying of its pay equity obligations some  
three years after they were undertaken, and just when significant difficulties  
that had stood in the way of their implementation were on the threshold of  
resolution. The importance of those pay equity promises is witnessed by the  
fact that, once assumed by Government, they become constitutionally  
protected fundamental rights. The finding of inimicalness in the attendant  
circumstances neither detracts from the significance of those rights, nor  
reflects any lack of appreciation of NAPE’s disappointment over  
Government’s reneger during the restraint periods, irrespective of the  
justifiability of that decision.  
[418] That said, the finding that the enjoyment of the promisees’ equality rights  
was inimical has to be viewed in the context of the length of, and reason for,  
limiting them. Hence, it needs be kept in mind that the violation was a  
temporary measure motivated by an urgent need to redress a severe  
Page: 152  
economic crisis confronting the Province. It has not been suggested that s. 9  
of the restraint legislation masks any colourable attempt to renege  
completely on the promises made in the Pay Equity Agreement of June 24,  
1988. In fact, as para. 3 of this judgment has already pointed out,  
arrangements were concluded on the expiry of the statutory restraint periods  
for the implementation of that Agreement. The inimicalness holding, then,  
only relates to the enjoyment of the fundamental constitutionally protected  
pay equity rights during the projected temporary three year period of  
restraints aimed at coping with a serious provincial emergency threatening  
the economic security and well-being of individuals and families within the  
jurisdiction. At the same time, the holding reflects the determination that  
the limitation placed on enjoyment of those equality rights conferred  
through the pay equity agreement was sufficiently important to justify  
temporarily overriding them through s. 9 of the restraint legislation.  
[419] Accordingly, the challenge to the judge’s upholding of the Arbitration  
Board’s unanimous finding of the restraint legislation’s sufficient  
importance is rejected. No exception may be taken with the judge’s  
determination that the “severe financial circumstances” looming over the  
Province rendered “the objective of reducing expenditures ... sufficiently  
important to justify a limitation on the s. 15(1) Charter rights”. Neither may  
objection be taken with his conclusion, implicit in that determination, that  
the Board’s holding in the same vein, highlighting the “pressing and  
substantial objective of saving money” in order “to reduce the escalating  
deficit ...”, was sustainable.  
[420] In the result, this judgment sides with the unanimous opinions expressed in  
all dispositions to date that the violation of the s. 15(1) equality rights  
secured through the Pay Equity Agreement was of sufficient importance for  
purposes of s. 1 justification under the Charter. The ultimate justification  
of the violation of the s. 15(1) Charter rights perpetrated through s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation comes down, therefore, to whether it is also sustainable  
under the three aspects of the proportionality criterion set down in Oakes.  
Before proceeding to that inquiry, however, as preceding para. 372  
indicated, attention will turn to the consonance of the Separation of Powers  
Doctrine with the foregoing analysis of the satisfaction of the first of the  
Oakes criteria.  
Page: 153  
>
consonance with the Doctrine:  
[421] In addressing the congruity of the Separation of Powers Doctrine with this  
judgment’s exercise of s. 1's judicial power, in the context of its affirmation  
of the prior findings that the objective of the s. 15(1) Charter violation  
perpetrated by s. 9 of the restraint legislation was important enough to  
justify the infringement, it needs to be underscored that that assessment took  
place on the footing of weighing the relative importance of the individual  
right contrasted with the communal objective of its violation, viz: the goal  
of containing and reducing the established threat of soaring fiscal deficits.  
No consideration was given in that inquiry, however, to alternate measures  
that might have been taken by Government. The exercise of deciding  
whether another course of action should have been followed, rather than the  
one which infringed the affected right, would be tantamount to the bench  
assuming policy powers to a degree not contemplated under s. 1 of the  
Charter. As has been repeatedly reiterated in this judgment, s. 1 of the  
Charter leaves justification of infringements to that “delicate balance”,  
which LaForest J. describes in the excerpt from his judgment in RJR-  
MacDonald reproduced in preceding para. 258, as having to be struck  
“between individual rights and community needs”. The comparison  
intended by s. 1, therefore, is confined to weighing the relative importance  
of enjoyment of the constitutionally protected right against Government’s  
actual policy choice to accord paramountcy to the societal objective that  
motivated the limitation on the right’s exercise, and not against another  
policy choice or objective.  
[422] It is important to keep in mind those confines of the scope of s. 1’s judicial  
sorties into the policy field. There is no doubt that s. 1 expanded the  
traditional role of the judiciary in the field of public policy coincidental with  
empowering courts to pass on the relative importance of the policy  
objectives behind rights’ violations vis à vis the enjoyment of those rights.  
However, it does not confer on the judiciary untrammelled license to usurp  
the policy domain of the elected branches of government beyond that point.  
Hence, whilst s. 1 empowers the judiciary to take that extra step into the  
policy field, it does not sanction further progression into the policy domain  
reserved to the political branches of government under the Separation of  
Powers Doctrine. As previously observed in this judgment, the Doctrine  
was not subsumed by s. 1, nor by any other provision of the Charter. They  
both constitute defining features of the Constitution, and are intended to  
Page: 154  
operate in rational harmony with each other in furthering the goals of a free  
and democratic society.  
[423] This harmony is achieved through judicial deference to the policy choice  
adopted to address communal or societal needs. That is not to say that courts  
must automatically defer to executive or legislative conclusions that  
communal ends were sufficiently important to justify violations of  
individual rights. Such determinations are squarely reserved to the judiciary  
under s. 1. It does mean, however, that the judiciary should defer to the  
opted policy choice, and not inquire into other alternatives whose  
realization might appear outweighed by the violated right’s enjoyment in  
striking that “delicate balance between individual rights and community  
needs” of which LaForest J. wrote in RJR-MacDonald.  
[424] Such deference is confirmed in the text of s. 1. A perusal of s. 1's wording  
reflects intent that the judicial justification power be rationalized through  
deference to the adopted policy choice without inquiry into other options  
which the judiciary might consider to have been available. Thus, the  
wording of s. 1 guarantees individual rights only to the extent that  
reasonable limits on their enjoyment are not proven demonstrably justifiable  
by societal objectives affecting their exercise. The Oakes criteria for s. 1's  
application should be received as intended to be applied in that light. This  
being so, in inquiries into whether collective goals of violative measures are  
important enough to warrant displacing or supplanting the affected  
individual right under s. 1, comparison would logically be expected to be  
between the exercise of the violated individual right and the collective  
objective that spawned the limitation on its exercise.  
[425] By the same token, s. 1 does not contemplate comparison of the  
fundamental individual right’s exercise with other policy choices that the  
judiciary might feel might have been adopted to respond to the communal or  
societal need. Such a course would stand the Separation of Powers Doctrine  
on its head, and the wording of s. 1 provides no basis for any such radical  
departure from it. Implicit in that wording is a call to judicial deference to  
the policy choice selected to achieve the collective goal, and concomitant  
direction to place only that choice, alongside the individual right which it  
violates on the scales of justification. Hence, whilst s. 1 undeniably  
modifies the Separation of Powers Doctrine as it operated before the  
Charter’s advent, to the extent of its warrant to inquire into the justifiability  
of the policy of the objective behind a Charter right’s violation, it holds the  
Page: 155  
judiciary’s incremental entry into the policy field to assessments of the  
justification of the actual policy choice which perpetrated the individual  
right’s limitation.  
[426] Moreover, in holding the assessment of the sufficiency of importance of the  
limitation on the individual right to comparison with the actual policy  
objective behind the limitation on the protected fundamental right, the  
Charter harmonizes the incremental judicial power in the policy domain  
conferred through s. 1 with the more longstanding feature of the  
Constitution embodied in the Doctrine. It so rationalizes those two defining  
constitutional features by confining the expanded judicial power within its  
rational bounds of passing on the justification of the selected policy choice  
to limit the individual right. Actually, it can be parenthetically observed  
that Oakes’ two criteria for s. 1 analyses can be seen to be melded in those  
two comparatives. Thus, in weighing the relative importance of the  
enjoyment of the individual right against the policy objective for limiting its  
exercise, the court is really engaged in an assessment of proportionality. In  
effect, inquiry into whether it has been established on a balance of  
probabilities that an intrusion into the enjoyment of a Charter right is  
important enough to justify overriding that right is essentially a cost/benefit  
analysis addressing whether it has been shown that, on the scale of relative  
importance, the cost of exercise of that right, would be disproportionate to  
the benefit derivable from the overriding limitation’s collective goal.  
[427] An essential key to conducting that analysis within the confines of its  
intended harmony with the Separation of Powers Doctrine lies in observing  
deference to the policy choice selected to achieve the collective societal  
goal, and not venturing into inquiry as to how alternate choices might weigh  
in the balance of justification. Although writing in partial dissent, another  
extract from Dickson C.J.C.’s judgment in PSAC provides sound rationale  
for underscoring the role that a high degree of deference to policy decisions  
plays in harmonizing s. 1 justifications with the Doctrine. Thus, at p. 442 of  
that authority he wrote:  
C
In my opinion, courts must exercise considerable caution when  
confronted with difficult questions of economic policy. It is not our  
judicial role to assess the effectiveness or wisdom of various  
government strategies for solving pressing economic problems. The  
question how best to combat inflation has perplexed economists for  
several generations. It would be highly undesirable for the courts to  
Page: 156  
attempt to pronounce on the relative importance of various suggested  
causes of inflation, such as the expansion of the money supply, fiscal  
deficits, foreign inflation or the built-in inflationary expectations of  
individual economic actors. A high degree of deference ought  
properly to be accorded to the government’s choice of strategy in  
combatting this complex problem.  
[428] The “high degree of deference” to governmental strategies for confronting  
“pressing economic problems” trumpeted in the foregoing passage was  
directed to the problem of controlling serious spiralling inflationary  
pressures, which was the objective that Dickson C.J.C. found sufficiently  
important in PSAC for the purpose of s. 1. It is equally germane, however,  
to problems presented by soaring fiscal deficits, which the case at bar  
involves. Moreover, while there appears to be no good reason why the  
cautionary note sounded in the foregoing passage, and its high level of  
judicial deference, should be confined to policy choices involving “difficult  
questions of economic policy”, it must, nonetheless, be counted especially  
so where those choices are made in reaction to menacing economic policies  
such as those confronted in PSAC and at bar. Those words of Dickson  
C.J.C. in PSAC make a strong case for high judicial deference to policy  
choices made by the executive or legislative branches in the context of  
rationalizing the expanded space allotted to the judiciary in the policy field  
by s. 1 with the Separation of Powers between the three branches of  
government, both of which are now essential features of the Canadian  
Constitution. As the foregoing passage from PSAC succinctly points out,  
while the judiciary is commissioned under s. 1 to pass upon the justifiability  
of the selected policy choice, it has no mandate, neither is it equipped, to be  
ultimate arbiter of the policy that should have been chosen in response to  
the complex problem.  
[429] Moreover, observance of a “high degree of deference” to the policy choice  
government opted to follow in the circumstances at bar does not run afoul of  
McLachlin J.’s view on deference articulated in RJR-MacDonald. As  
preceding para. 267 records, McLachlin J. held in that authority that a lesser  
degree of deference is accordable “where the trial judge has considered  
social science and other policy oriented evidence” as opposed “to findings  
based on evidence of a purely factual nature”. While the legislative  
objective of curbing fiscal deficits was itself aimed at maintaining the  
Province’s capacity to provide educational, health, and other social services  
Page: 157  
and communal needs, the evidence bearing upon the justification of that  
objective vis à vis the limitation of the Charter equality rights effectuated  
by s. 9 of the restraint legislation was not based on considerations of “social  
science and other policy oriented evidence”. Instead, the evidence upon  
which the justification findings were unanimously reached in the two prior  
proceedings was based on cold, hard economic realities. In one sense, all  
evidence leading to policy decisions might be characterized as “policy  
oriented” as it was the basis of the choice. However, it appears McLachlin  
J.’s holding should be read in the sense of the evidence itself having a  
policy context. The fact that RJR-MacDonald addressed a legislative  
choice requiring warning labels on tobacco which was justifiable on policy-  
oriented evidence, and not “difficult questions of economic policy”  
justifiable on fiscal evidence of a factual nature, distinguishes that case from  
the circumstances at bar. In any event, the policy choice under scrutiny in  
this appeal was taken on factual evidence which, as McLachlin J. confirms,  
normally requires a high level of deference.  
[430] In the result, therefore, a high degree of deference to the policy choice  
effectuated through s. 9 of the restraint legislation requires the violation of  
the public sector employees’ s. 15(1) Charter equality rights being weighed  
on the scale of s. 1 justification against that choice, and no other. Because  
the evidence motivating that choice consisted of hard economic realities of a  
factual nature, high deference is also accordable to those findings, as well.  
It needs be added, however, that on any level of deference those findings  
would have to be sustained. In fact, given that the omnipresence of the  
looming serious fiscal deficits was inescapable, the evidence behind the  
policy choice to impose the limits on the pay equity entitlements through s.  
9 would be sustainable on any lesser degree of deference, or even on the  
more stringent standard of correctness.  
[431] Accordingly, this judgment concludes the judge should be upheld in his  
affirmation of the Board’s unanimous finding that the objective of s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation was sufficiently important to justify its violation of the  
affected employee’s s. 15(1) equality rights. It has also taken, as it indicated  
it would in preceding para. 372, the added step of explaining how that  
conclusion was reached without invading the policy domain reserved to the  
other branches of government under the Separation of Powers Doctrine as  
modified by the operation of s. 1 of the Charter. Hence, it can also be  
concluded that the determination that the legislative objective was  
Page: 158  
sufficiently important to justify overriding the affected equality rights was  
carried out in consonance with the Doctrine. Having made these findings,  
this s. 1 analysis turns to the second of the Oakes criteria, i.e., the  
proportionality aspect of justifications of Charter rights violations.  
>
proportionality of measures:  
[432] The foregoing inquiry into whether the objective of s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation was sufficiently important to justify its violation of affected  
employees’ s. 15(1) Charter equality rights naturally focused on the  
relative importance of that objective compared with the enjoyment of those  
equality rights. From a survey of relevant authorities canvassed in  
preceding paras. 379 to 409, this judgment explains why that focus in  
analysis of the first of the Oakes criteria does not converge on the means of  
attaining communal objectives, but on the societal goals themselves. Thus,  
in the initial phase of s. 1 analyses, the degree of the objective’s importance  
is matched against the import of the limitation of the Charter right or  
freedom perpetrated in the realization of those societal goals. Through this  
comparison it is determined whether the objective is “sufficiently  
significant” to outweigh the acknowledged importance of the individual  
fundamental right or freedom that will be breached in the course of realizing  
the purpose of the societal objective.  
[433] On the other hand, inquiry into proportionality - the other of the two central  
criteria laid down in Oakes for the conduct of s. 1 analyses - focuses on the  
means, or the measure, by which the objective is achieved. This focus is  
gleanable in the following excerpt at p. 139 of Oakes, setting out three  
components of the proportionality test:  
C
... once a sufficiently significant objective is recognized, then the  
party invoking s. 1 must show that the means chosen are reasonable  
and demonstrably justified. This involves “a form of proportionality  
test” ... Although the nature of the proportionality test will vary  
depending on the circumstances, in each case courts will be required  
to balance the interests of society with those of individuals and  
groups. There are, in my view, three important components of a  
proportionality test. First, the measures adopted must be carefully  
designed to achieve the objective in question. They must not be  
arbitrary, unfair or based on irrational considerations. In short, they  
must be rationally connected to the objective. Second, the means,  
Page: 159  
even if rationally connected to the objective in this first sense, should  
impair “as little as possible” the right or freedom in question. Third,  
there must be a proportionality between the effects of the measures  
which are responsible for limiting the Charter right or freedom, and  
the objective which has been identified as of “sufficient importance”.  
[434] As can be observed from a perusal of the foregoing excerpt, the comparative  
common to all three components on the proportionality side of the inquiry is  
the measure taken to achieve the objective. Hence, the primary focus at this  
second proportionality stage of the analysis switches from the objective to  
the means taken to attain it. The foregoing passage instructs that three  
components must constitute the measure. Firstly, it must be shown it is  
fairly and rationally relatable to attainability of its objective, which already  
will have been established as sufficiently important to justify the Charter  
limitation, and does not constitute an arbitrary exercise of executive or  
legislative power. Secondly, the measure must impair the affected right or  
freedom “as little as possible”; or, as it is sometimes expressed, is the “least  
drastic means” of intruding on that right or freedom. Finally, with the  
importance criterion together with the rational connection and minimal  
impairment components of the proportionality test resolved, the measure is  
weighed to determine if the effects of its limitation on the constitutionally  
guaranteed right or freedom is, nonetheless, so deleterious as to outweigh its  
substantial and pressing objective. It will be noted, then, that it is the  
degree of the measure’s proportionality in relation to its objective that is  
taken into account in considering the first and third components, whilst its  
degree vis à vis the affected right or freedom is the axis of comparison in  
broaching the second component.  
[435] The opening words in that highlighted excerpt from Oakes are also  
noteworthy. As they state, the degree of the objective’s importance will  
have been established by the time the proportionality requirements come for  
consideration. Otherwise, the violation would have had to have been held  
unjustifiable and there would be no need to enter into that second stage of  
the analysis. At that juncture, with the degree of its importance being  
settled as “sufficiently significant” to justify overriding the limitation on the  
constitutionally protected right or freedom, the objective of the infringing  
measure takes its place with the affected right or freedom as an end of  
recognized importance. Thus, together with the right or freedom that has  
been limited, it becomes a fixed yardstick with which the proportionality of  
Page: 160  
the measure is respectively weighed in the context of the proportionality  
test’s “three important components”. In effect, then, to coin a well known  
colloquialism, all three components essentially involve inquiry directed  
towards assuring that no collective mallet is used to kill the proverbial fly  
by resort to disproportionate means to realize professed paramount  
collective goals at the unjustifiable expense of constitutionally protected  
individual rights.  
[436] Against the backdrop of the foregoing commentary, this judgment will now  
proceed to apply the second of the Oakes criteria, following the format of  
the three components into which that authority divides the proportionality  
test. It perhaps should be mentioned that previously in this judgment these  
components, following the terminology employed in referenced decisions  
then under discussion, have been alternately referred to as criteria, or  
aspects, or principles, or guidelines. This lack of consistency in  
terminology is neither here nor there insofar as the substance of the  
components’ application is concerned. It is noted, however, for explanatory  
purposes, if that be needed. Henceforth, the three defined elements of the  
test described in the excerpt from Oakes reproduced in preceding para. 433  
will be referred to as components in the ensuing proportionality analysis.  
>
rational connection component:  
overview of inquiry:  
*
[437] In addressing the first of these proportionality components, inquiry turns, in  
accordance with the direction in the highlighted excerpt from Oakes, to  
whether the measure repealing government’s obligations to make the pay  
equity adjustments over the restraint periods is rationally connected to the  
legislative objective of containing and reducing the fiscal deficits that  
threatened the economic security and well-being of everyone in the  
Province. As just explained in outlining the format of the inquiry, this will  
entail consideration of whether the repeal was fairly and rationally relatable  
to containing and reducing those forecastable deficits, or masked an  
arbitrary exercise of power. It should be underscored that this inquiry is  
undertaken in the context of addressing the sustainability of the judge’s  
holding that the unanimous finding of the Arbitration Board of rational  
connection of the measure to the objective should be upheld.  
Page: 161  
[438] At the outset, it must be observed that it would appear to strain the limits of  
logic beyond their bounds to suggest that such fiscal restraint was not  
rationally connected to the legislation’s objective of containing and  
reducing the fiscal deficits that loomed over the Province. Just as every  
spendthrift practice, be it familial or governmental, sows seeds of spiralling  
deficits, and of economic hardships which such deficits inevitably presage,  
so it would seem axiomatically to follow that restraints on expenditures are  
rationally connected to the curbing of fiscal deficits, and to avoidance of the  
heavy burdens arising out of consequential deteriorating economic  
conditions.  
*
positions of counsel:  
[439] In her client’s factum, counsel for NAPE maintained Government had failed  
to demonstrate it was necessary to impair the constitutional rights at issue in  
this case in order to fulfill its objective of reducing governmental  
expenditures. The factum went on to contend the evidence adduced before  
the Arbitration Board does not contradict NAPE’s claim that that objective  
could have been met without enacting s. 9 of the restraint measure.  
Although this stance in the Union’s factum appears to border more so on the  
minimal impairment component of the proportionality test, NAPE’s factum  
submitted the alleged lack of demonstrable necessity sustained a conclusion  
that no rational connection had been established.  
[440] In his response to these formal submissions by NAPE, counsel for  
Government holds up the words of Dickson C.J.C. in the Oakes extract  
reproduced in preceding para. 433 which underscores measures “must be  
carefully designed to achieve the objective in question ... must not be  
arbitrary, unfair or based on irrational considerations”. Government’s  
factum maintains that the “postponed pay equity payments” effected by s. 9  
of the restraint legislation were “carefully tailored to achieve its object and  
was neither arbitrary nor irrational”. It is noted that this argument  
substantially tracks the judge’s finding regarding fulfillment of the rational  
connection argument which, in turn, followed the view on that aspect of the  
s. 1 analysis of the Board’s majority.  
*
measure’s rational connection:  
[441] There appears to be no need for protracted discussion of these arguments.  
In Re: Anti-Inflation Act, [1976] 2 S.C.R. 373, which has already been  
Page: 162  
referred to in the passage from Dickson C.J.C.’s judgment in PSAC  
reproduced in preceding para. 397, Laskin C.J.C. held at p. 425 that  
“Parliament’s stern intervention in the interests of the country as a whole”,  
through the legislative anti-inflationary measure, was rationally connected  
to the enactment’s objective of meeting “a situation of economic crisis  
imperilling the well-being of the people of Canada as a whole”. Inasmuch  
as this holding was sufficient for the Court to have ruled that Parliament had  
a justifiable “rational basis” to regard the measure as “temporarily  
necessary” to warrant invoking its emergency legislative powers, there  
appears to be ample room to justifiably argue by analogy the rational  
connection of the temporary reneging on the pay equity payments in order to  
combat the economic crisis presented by incipient escalating deficits, and to  
consider the measure necessary in the interests of the Province as a whole.  
[442] In the final analysis, counsel for NAPE did not deny the common sense of  
the rational connection of the restraint measure with its legislative object.  
Thus, in her oral submissions she conceded that, if the enactment’s  
objective was to save money, it would be difficult to maintain that s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation was not rationally connected to its objective. This  
forthrightness is timely. No other conclusion could be drawn in the  
circumstances of this case. While the saving of money was not, strictly  
speaking, the legislative objective, but the means to its end of containing  
and reducing serious fiscal deficits hovering over the Province, the measure  
must be conceded to have been rationally connected to that objective. This  
is established by the evidence which shows the restraint measure limiting  
enjoyment of affected employees’ s. 15(1) Charter rights to be fairly and  
rationally relatable to the attainment of its objective, and which offers no  
basis to portray the measure as a colourable attempt to arbitrarily trench on  
those rights.  
*
consonance with Doctrine:  
[443] The foregoing conclusion of rational connection has been reached in consort  
with the Separation of Powers Doctrine. This is because it involved no  
inquiry into whether other means existed that might be perceived more  
rationally connected to the legislative object. Conforming with the call to  
deference to legislative policy choices, the foregoing assessment was strictly  
confined to the linkage of the statutory choice to postpone the  
commencement of pay equity adjustments with the objective of the statutory  
Page: 163  
measure. The conclusion of rational connection, therefore, can be seen as  
made in the course of exercise of judicial power which is akin to the court’s  
traditional statutory interpretative role of construing the effect of measures  
having the force of law. In that light, alternate measures formed no part of  
the reasoning, and the conclusion was made within acceptable bounds, in  
consonance with both s. 1 and the Doctrine as it has traditionally operated.  
*
affirmation of findings:  
[444] Accordingly, the judge’s upholding of the Board’s unanimous ruling that  
the restraint measure was “well tailored to suit its purpose” is sustainable.  
In the result, agreement must be voiced with the unanimous finding to date  
that the legislative restraint measure reneging on the promises to make the  
pay equity adjustments during the restraint periods was rationally connected  
with its legislative objective. Hence, the judge’s holding that the first of the  
Oakes proportionality components was affirmable is sustainable. The  
foregoing reasoning not only satisfies that aspect of the s. 1 analysis, but  
also is consonant with the Separation of Powers Doctrine.  
>
minimal impairment component:  
recap of decisions:  
*
[445] As the summaries of the decisions of the Arbitration Board panel provided  
earlier in this judgment show, the Chairperson concluded the minimal  
impairment component of the proportionality test had not been met. For  
reasons summarized in preceding paras. 31 and 32 he found that  
government might have considered, at most, “only one alternative to the  
infringement”. Thus, after mentioning that the Leader of the Opposition  
had proposed some thirteen other alternatives, and the Treasury Board  
Secretary had attested to “other money-saving mechanisms”, the  
Chairperson wrote in conclusion “there was more than sufficient evidence”  
of “several other less restrictive means” available to Government.  
[446] Government’s nominee to the panel, on the other hand, differed with the  
conclusion that the minimal impairment component of the proportionality  
criterion had not been met. As preceding para. 47 relates, he essentially  
rested his decision on deference. Hence, whilst conceding other means  
were available, he maintained it lies neither with the courts, nor with  
arbitrators, to substitute “their opinions for the collective wisdom of the  
Page: 164  
Legislature” with respect to the allocation of “scarce resources between  
competing but legitimate groups”. Immediately before this reasoning,  
Government’s nominee had placed stock in the fact that “a total ban” had  
not been placed “on pay equity agreements” by the impugned legislation,  
but it “merely eliminated retroactive payments in a time of fiscal  
restraint...”.  
[447] As preceding para. 44 mentions, NAPE’s nominee on the panel concurred  
with the Chairperson’s Charter disposition, making the latter’s resolution  
of failure to meet the minimal impairment test the majority conclusion of the  
Board. However, for reasons set out in the extract from his judgment  
reproduced in preceding para. 79, the judge did not share the majority view  
with respect to minimal impairment. In departing from the Board’s findings  
regarding this phase of the proportionality text, the judge underscored that  
the majority had overlooked the Minister’s “extended budgetary  
explanation” in which the latter had widely canvassed the alternatives  
considered by Government in response to its menacing deficitary problem.  
Consequently, the judge overturned the Board’s finding on the second  
component of the proportionality test, and held the Legislature had made  
reasonable effort to minimize the infringement of the s. 15(1) Charter  
rights when it delayed implementation of the promised pay equity through  
enactment of s. 9 of the restraint legislation.  
*
counsel’s submissions:  
[448] Citing authorities to make her point that analysis of satisfaction of the  
minimal impairment component requires proof that Government turned its  
mind to alternative and less rights-impairing means to further the goal  
which intruded on the affected Charter right or freedom, counsel for NAPE  
maintains the judge failed to appreciate that Government fell short of  
acquitting its obligation to demonstrate it could not have met its objective of  
combatting the deficit problem in any way less intrusive on the affected  
constitutionally protected equality rights. Styling Government’s evidence in  
that regard as “extremely weak”, NAPE’s counsel made extensive  
references to the arbitration transcript to substantiate her position.  
Emphasizing that Government called only two public servants to testify,  
counsel construes their testimony as speaking, in one instance, exclusively  
to the expense of pay equity, and points to the other as explicitly  
acknowledging he was in no position to testify regarding the alternatives  
Page: 165  
Cabinet might have considered. Depicting the transcript as establishing a  
complete dearth of evidence respecting consideration of alternate measures,  
counsel insists Government failed to prove it turned its mind to this  
essential concern, without which no holding of minimal impairment could  
be made.  
[449] Describing minimal impairment as the “meat” of the proportionality test,  
Government’s counsel responds by insisting that concentration of inquiry  
into that component’s fulfillment should, as Dickson C.J.C. indicated in p.  
772 of Edwards Books, be directed to whether the measure abridges the  
Charter right or freedom “as little as is reasonably possible”. This being  
so, counsel suggests the component might more accurately be described as  
the “least drastic means”, which is the term sometimes employed.  
Favouring that terminology, counsel reasons it to be better than minimal  
impairment which tends to funnel inquiry into whether another means might  
have been employed, and inevitably leads to inquiries into alternate  
measures. Arguing that another way can usually be found, he maintains the  
test is the reasonableness of the action taken, and not whether alternate  
measures might be considered by the Court to more minimally impair the  
affected right or freedom. Stressing that the judge had used the term “least  
drastic means” in his discussion of this phase of the proportionality test, and  
noting the decision under appeal spoke of “reasonable effort” to minimize  
the infringement by delaying pay equity implementation, rather than  
eliminating it, counsel argues this was the proper approach inasmuch as it  
observed appropriate deference, the application of which mandated  
upholding the judge’s conclusion that the minimal impairment component  
of the proportionality test was satisfied in the circumstances of this appeal.  
[450] It will be readily apparent that this part of Government counsel’s argument  
centers on the measure actually adopted to achieve the legislative objective  
of combatting the deficitary problems then enshrouding the Province, and  
engages no consideration of alternate measures. In so doing, it follows the  
same approach which was adopted in preceding paras. 421 to 431 whilst  
addressing the rational connection component of the proportionality test,  
which approach is supported in the wording of s. 1 as well as being in  
harmony with the Separation of Powers Doctrine. Moreover, this phase of  
counsel’s rejoinder to the attack on the judge’s treatment of the minimal  
impairment question can be seen to track the reasoning of the Government  
nominee to the Arbitration Board which is summarized in preceding para.  
Page: 166  
446. Thus, as can be seen from a perusal of his reasoning, the Government  
nominee, in his analysis of the minimal impairment component, also had  
aligned himself with the approach of confining consideration to the measure  
actually adopted, and abstains from inquiry into alternate means, in  
underscoring that s. 9 of the restraint legislation “merely eliminated  
retroactive payments in a time of fiscal restraint”, and did not impose a  
“total ban”, and in resting his decision on deference to the choice  
implemented in s. 9.  
[451] Government counsel’s rebuttal of the challenge to the judge’s disposition of  
the minimal impairment question did not end at that juncture, however.  
Thus, he directly addressed opposing counsel’s contention that the evidence  
was too weak to support the judge’s finding by insisting her argument  
ignores the Hansard record of the ministerial statements on introduction of  
the restraint measure in the Assembly, and disregards as well the budgetary  
exhibits which were placed in evidence before the Arbitration Board.  
Quoting liberally from the judge’s references to the statements by the  
Minister of Finance recorded in the Hansard, included in which was the  
passage from the decision under appeal reproduced in para. 79 of this  
judgment, counsel maintains there had been ample evidence adduced of a  
full consideration given by Government to alternative measures, and that the  
judge’s finding to that effect in overturning the Board majority’s contrary  
view on minimal impairment was unassailable.  
[452] In addressing these positions, this judgment will first deal with the alternate  
measures arguments which was the basis of NAPE’s challenge of the  
judge’s minimal impairment disposition. Then, it will take up the argument  
which focuses exclusively on the minimal impairment of the measure  
actually implemented which was advanced by Government counsel.  
Following these discussions, the consonance of the results with the  
Separation of Powers Doctrine will be addressed.  
*
alternate measures:  
[453] It was quite logical for NAPE’s counsel to have presented her critique of the  
judge’s minimal impairment analysis without reference to Hansard.  
Counsel for NAPE is contesting in a separate ground of appeal the judge’s  
rejection of her attack on the Arbitration Board’s use of Hansard. As the  
format for the treatment of the issues in this appeal set out in preceding  
para. 108 indicates, that challenge will be addressed in the second last of the  
Page: 167  
issues under discussion in this judgment. In the meantime, as has been  
earlier stated, this analysis into whether the infringement perpetrated by s. 9  
of the restraint legislation was saved under s. 1 of the Charter proceeds,  
arguendo at this juncture, on the footing that the judge properly resorted to  
Hansard, from which, as preceding paras. 79 and 447 record, he took  
account of the Minister of Finance’s “extended budgetary explanation”.  
[454] A perusal of that Minister’s “extended budgetary explanation” in Hansard  
provides ample ground of support for the judge’s conclusion that  
“Government had considered various alternatives such as borrowing, tax  
increases, budget freezes and reduction in Government expenditures”.  
Thus, the Hansard of March 19, 1991, records the Minister as indicating  
resort to borrowing was ruled out in response to the crisis because it was  
decided “(w)e no longer had that luxury. We could not take the chance that  
our credit rating would drop another notch”. Later, he went on to add it  
would be taking “too great a chance on the financial health of the Province”  
to entertain the notion of increased borrowings. With respect to tax  
increases, the Minister is also reported to have informed the Assembly,  
whilst tentative agreement had been reached to impose some tax measures,  
the amount recoverable from that source was “far short of what we had to  
do”. As to the alternative of a general budgetary freeze, Hansard documents  
the Minister as stating:  
C
One thing became obvious, very obvious, that the objectives of a  
frozen budget could not be maintained. We could not inflict a frozen  
budget on all parts of the our public service. The budget for hospitals  
could not be frozen. The budget for primary and elementary schools  
could not be frozen. The budget for social services could not be  
frozen. We could not inflict a frozen budget ....  
[455] The Government also had agreed to some expenditure reductions.  
However, the Minister’s “extended budgetary explanation” indicates that,  
apart from freezing then subsisting wage scales, and eliminating its liability  
for the “retroactive bill” for pay equity that was building up pending  
ascertainment of its amount on receipt of the then awaited financial  
consultants report, and which Government was estimating to be “in the  
vicinity of $24 million”, there was no scope for further reductions. Thus,  
the Minister explained that apart from these measures, Government  
confronted:  
Page: 168  
C
... the spectre of laying off another couple of thousand people, and we  
felt that the system would demand that we not lay off another 2000  
people, that the services we are providing would have to be  
drastically affected.  
[456] Hence, the speech of the Minister of Finance on introduction of the restraint  
legislation left no room to Government which was faced with “difficult  
choices” in its efforts to combat the critical fiscal circumstances confronting  
the Province. Moreover, there appears to be no room to gainsay from a  
perusal of Hansard that it supports the judge’s conclusion that the “extended  
budgetary explanations” establish Government canvassed a broad spectrum  
of alternate measures, and not “only one alternative to the infringement”, as  
the chairperson of the Arbitration Board had portrayed Government’s  
reaction.  
[457] It is true that the same Hansard records that the Leader of the Opposition  
proposed other alternate measures. It is also true that the transcript shows  
the Arbitration Board heard evidence from a public servant relative to  
“other money-saving mechanisms”. However, in the parliamentary system,  
the introduction of policy initiatives as governmental measures for  
legislative sanction of policy measures lies within the executive’s purview.  
Hence, only the Minister responsible for a measure, or a Cabinet colleague  
speaking on his or her behalf, is in a position to speak to what alternate  
policy choices were considered by the Executive Council. Likewise, public  
servants may relate other courses, but are in no position to testify regarding  
the policy choices considered at cabinet, nor the rationale for the choices  
made. For these reasons, with due respect, the Arbitration Board’s majority  
erred in adverting to the Opposition’s proposal and the Treasury Board  
secretary’s evidence in concluding the minimal impairment component of  
the proportionality test had not been met.  
[458] The foregoing observation should not be taken to detract in any way from  
the role’s which the Opposition and the Public Service play in the  
governmental process. In particular, it is recognized it is clearly an  
Opposition’s function to propose reasonable alternate measures to those  
being put forth by the Ministry. It is mandated to do so in a democracy,  
whereas the judiciary is not. In discharging its mandate, the Opposition  
could conceivably bring to light considerations clearly overlooked that  
undermine the Ministry’s claim to have canvassed all reasonable  
alternatives to the Charter infringement. If this be so, then its contribution  
Page: 169  
to the debate will have significant bearing upon whether all reasonable  
efforts were addressed to minimize the Charter infringement. More likely,  
however, the Opposition will have proposed other alternatives to the  
Ministry’s policy choices that appear reasonable in themselves, but must be  
reckoned as being put forth as preferred alternatives.  
[459] That said, the judiciary must be cautious in its treatment of alternate  
measures proposed on the Opposition side in such debates. Neither s. 1, nor  
any other provision of the Charter, nor the Constitution itself of which the  
Charter is now an integral part, bestow authority on the judiciary to  
determine which policy choices should have been preferred by the executive  
or legislative branches of government. That is a decision ultimately  
reserved in free and democratic societies for the electorate, which is  
afforded opportunity to speak through the ballot box. In executing its  
commission under s. 1, the law as it presently stands accepts that the  
judiciary’s function is to determine if the minimal impairment component of  
the proportionality test has been demonstrably justified from the standpoint  
of alternate measures. This is essentially determinable by inquiry into  
whether the executive and legislature considered reasonable alternatives in  
taking the policy choice which materialized in the impugned statutory  
enactment. If it be established reasonable alternatives had been considered,  
then a healthy deference to that choice is required to be observed by the  
courts.  
[460] In the appeal at bar, the Hansard provides no basis to view the alternatives  
proposed by Her Majesty’s alternate Government as more than preferred  
options, regardless of how reasonable they might appear. It lies with neither  
administrative nor judicial tribunals to decide which of the reasonable  
optional alternatives proposed from the opposite sides of legislative  
chambers should be preferred. In the case of statutory measures violative of  
protected constitutional rights, the focus is on the considerations addressed  
by the Executive Council prior to submitting its policy choice as a  
legislative measure for enactment. This being the case, a reliable source of  
the alternatives considered would naturally be the address of the Minister  
responsible for piloting the measure through the Legislature. The judge in  
this case relied heavily on that source. The Hansard that was put before him  
accords no outlet to take exception with his holding that “various  
alternatives such as borrowing, tax increases, budget freezes and reductions  
in expenditures” had been considered in the course of the Ministry’s  
Page: 170  
decision to introduce the restraint legislation limiting the enjoyment of pay  
equity and the affected employees s. 15(1) Charter rights. Indeed, these  
options, as expanded upon by the Minister of Finance in his recorded  
“extended budgetary explanation”, may be viewed as essentially covering  
the whole gamut of alternatives that might be considered as reasonable to  
have been addressed. Nor does the Hansard at bar provide ground to take  
issue with the judge’s conclusion of error on the part of the Board’s majority  
that just one alternative, i.e. the lay-off of approximately 900 employees,  
had been considered.  
[461] Accordingly, from the perspective of alternative measures, the judge must  
be upheld in his overturing of the Arbitration Board’s majority decision  
holding Government had failed to establish it had a reasonable basis for  
concluding that the means chosen to address restraint through the  
postponement of the pay equity was demonstrably justifiable as a minimal  
impairment.  
*
the measure adopted:  
[462] In the context of this inquiry into the minimal impairment component, it  
remains to consider Government counsel’s argument, summarized in  
preceding paras. 449 and 450, which focuses on the measure actually  
adopted, and engages no consideration of alternate measures.  
[463] Support for such a confined approach to minimal impairment analyses is  
drawable from Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (A.G.), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927  
where a ban on commercial advertising directed at children under thirteen  
years of age was held to infringe freedom of expression guaranteed under s.  
2(b) of the Charter, and accordingly underwent s. 1 analysis. In discussing  
the proportionality test, inquiry was directed to whether the specific means  
of banning the advertising minimally impaired the violated freedom.  
Towards the end of that discussion, at p. 999, Dickson C.J.C. concluded:  
C
... the evidence sustains the reasonableness of the legislature’s  
conclusion that a ban on commercial advertising directed to children  
was the minimal impairment of free expression consistent with the  
pressing and substantial goal of protecting children against  
manipulation through such advertising.  
Page: 171  
As can be seen in the above excerpt from Irwin Toy, the minimal impairment  
component inquiry was addressed by comparison of the specific measure, i.e. the  
commercial advertising ban, with its end of child protection.  
[464] Likewise, in the circumstances at bar, the evidence sustains the judge’s  
conclusion that the measure actually adopted of postponing enjoyment of  
the pay equity adjustments for the duration of the restraint period was the  
minimal impairment of the affected employees’ s. 15(1) equality rights  
consistent with the pressingly important goal of containing and reducing the  
incipient fiscal deficits confronting the Province. This conclusion of  
minimal impairment is sustainable because, as Government counsel argues,  
the evidence establishes the limitation on the affected s. 15(1) equality  
rights, perpetrated by s. 9 of the restraint legislation, abridged enjoyment of  
them “as little as possible”. As counsel maintains, in words which echo the  
reasoning of the Government nominee to the Arbitration Board, support for  
the judge’s conclusion stems from the fact that s. 9 imposed no “total ban”,  
but “merely eliminated retroactive payment in a time of fiscal restraint”.  
Hence, from the perspective of weighing the degree of the adopted  
measure’s impairment of the affected equality rights, which preceding para.  
434 extracts from Oakes to be the proper focus in analyses of the second  
proportionality component, agreement has to be voiced with counsel’s  
submission that the s. 9 measure was the “least drastic means” of intruding  
on those constitutional rights.  
[465] That agreement can be lent because, consideration of alternate measures  
aside, the fact that the impugned legislation delayed pay equity  
implementation rather than eliminating it witnesses that “reasonable effort”  
was made to minimize the infringement. In the context of the circumstances  
of that deferral, this would appear to be enough. With such a conclusion  
judicial deference comes into play. It was problematic whether the  
Arbitration Board, or the Court, could delve into the existence of other  
alternatives which should have appeared more preferable to the legislators  
without assuming their seats and paying mere lip service to judicial  
deference. The fact that there was no “total ban”, but the infringement was  
contained by eliminating the “retroactive payments in a time of fiscal  
restraint”, stands, in itself, as sufficient proof of minimal impairment.  
[466] An interesting distinction exists which merits passing mention between the  
minimal impairment reasoning in Irwin Toy and its analysis in the  
circumstances at bar. Thus, in Irwin Toy, a permanent limitation on  
Page: 172  
enjoyment of the affected right was found to justify the minimal impairment  
finding, whilst in the matter at hand the fact that the limiting restriction was  
not a permanent “total ban” is a factor material to the finding. This is no  
paradox, however, but rather serves both to illustrate that Charter analyses  
are circumstantially oriented, and to underscore the purposive approach to  
them that courts have been directed to employ in the earliest authorities  
setting down guidelines for the Charter analyses.  
*
consonance with Doctrine:  
[467] As to the extra step undertaken here of vetting the consonance of the  
reasoning of each stage of this s. 1 analysis with the Separation of Powers  
Doctrine, contrary to the two prior assessments relating to that concern,  
differing conclusions emerge from the foregoing minimal impairment  
reasoning.  
[468] As in the kindred inquiries at the end of the findings of the sufficiency of  
the objective’s importance and the rational connection of its means, the  
second line of the minimal impairment reasoning centered on the measure  
actually adopted, without advertence to alternate options. In so doing, that  
reasoning stayed within the Doctrine’s bounds as modified by s. 1 of the  
Charter which, as this judgment argues in preceding paras. 421 to 431,  
confines incremental judicial incursions into the policy field to choices  
actually made by exacting deference to them in justification analyses.  
[469] It should be underscored that in that second line of reasoning the minimal  
impairment component is addressed by focusing on the restraint actually  
implemented, through s. 9 of the impugned legislation, on the enjoyment of  
pay equity. It does not venture into other policy choices which  
hypothetically might have been made. Appropriate deference is observed,  
and inquiry centers on whether the measure itself could yet have been  
tailored to more minimal impact on the constitutional right which was  
violated. As preceding para. 443 indicates was the case with the rational  
connection finding, in abstaining from inquiry whether other measures  
existed which might have been perceived to less minimally impair the s.  
15(1) equality rights, and in strictly centering focus on the measure actually  
adopted, the conclusion reached under the second line of reasoning that the  
second component of the proportionality test had been fulfilled was also  
reached in consonance with the Separation of Powers Doctrine.  
Page: 173  
[470] The same conclusion cannot be drawn with respect to the firstly discussed  
line of reasoning, however. It centers on inquiry whether the evidence  
established other options had been considered before the policy choice was  
made to postpone pay equity by means of the impugned restraint measure.  
As the discussion of the division in RJR-MacDonald over the  
proportionality requirements enunciated in Oakes in preceding paras. 354 to  
368 underscores, it is difficult to conceive how such focus can be  
maintained without frequently transcending the legitimate bounds to judicial  
policy-making. This is especially so in the case of the minimal impairment  
component if, as preceding paras. 358 and 359 point out, that requirement is  
to be applied by considering whether legislatures turned their minds to  
alternate less rights-impairing means to promote their goals.  
[471] Despite these misgivings over the first line of reasoning which rests  
fulfillment of the minimal impairment component of the proportionality test  
on a survey of alternate measures, it is recognized it reflects extant law to  
which administrative and judicial tribunals must pay obeisance. The judge  
was correct in doing so. He was also right in overruling the Arbitration  
Board’s holding that Government had failed to show it had a reasonable  
basis to conclude it had complied with the minimal impairment component  
of proportionality. No exception can be taken with the judge’s assertion  
that that holding overlooked the extended ministerial budgetary explanation,  
and erred in failing to appreciate that alternative measures had been  
considered beyond the single consideration of laying-off approximately 900  
employees. In the result the judge’s ruling that the Legislature had “made a  
reasonable effort to minimize the infringement of the Section 15(1) Charter  
right when it chose, in Section 9 of the Act, to delay implementation of the  
Pay Equity Agreement” is sustainable on that basis. It needs to be added  
that it is also affirmable by focusing exclusively on the measure actually  
adopted which, as the ensuing discussion indicates, is the approach  
preferred by this judgment.  
[472] In the result, no exception can be taken under subsisting jurisprudence with  
the judge having based his finding that the minimal impairment component  
of the proportionality test has been met, on the basis of the survey of  
alternate measures conducted by the Executive Council, in reaching its  
policy choice to postpone pay equity, which was given the force of law  
through the Legislature’s enactment of s. 9 of the restraint legislation. On  
that footing, the judge committed no error in overruling the Arbitration  
Page: 174  
Board’s holding that Government has failed to show it had a reasonable  
basis to conclude it had complied with the minimal impairment component  
of proportionality. The judge’s holding that the Board’s majority had  
overlooked the “extended budgetary explanations” of the Minister of  
Finance is unimpeachable. This judgment argues, however, that no pretense  
can be made that the alternate measures pathway of inquiry is consonant  
with the Separation of Powers Doctrine. Because of that inconsonance, it is  
submitted that the second of the two foregoing arguments confining  
consideration exclusively to the measure actually implemented is the  
preferable basis for finding compliance with minimal impairment.  
Page: 175  
*
minimal impairment’s disposition:  
[473] For the foregoing reasons, the judge’s overturning of the Arbitration  
Board’s majority ruling that the minimal impairment component of the  
proportionality test had not been met should be upheld. The judge was  
correct in concluding that the ruling omitted to take into account the  
extended ministerial budgetary explanation of the alternate measures that  
had been considered when the policy choice to limit pay equity entitlements  
was made. On the basis of the Hansard evidence detailing the options  
considered, no exception can be taken under subsisting jurisprudence with  
the judge’s finding that adequate proof had been adduced of reasonable  
efforts to minimize the infringement of the s. 15(1) Charter rights when it  
delayed implementation of the promised pay equity.  
[474] Neither may exception be taken with concluding that the postponement  
measure actually adopted, apart altogether from alternate measures  
considerations, can be regarded as a reasonable effort to minimize the  
infringement. As will already be clear from the preceding discussion, this  
judgment submits that avenue of inquiry is preferable because it can be  
made without untoward judicial disruption of the Separation of Powers  
feature of the Constitution.  
[475] On both accounts, therefore, the judge’s ruling that the Legislature had  
“made a reasonable effort to minimize the infringement of the Section 15(1)  
Charter right when it chose, in s. 9 of the Act, to delay implementation of  
the Pay Equity Agreement” is affirmable. It now remains to address the  
third and final component of the s. 1 proportionality test.  
>
proportionality of effects:  
the ultimate determinant:  
*
[476] Although the Charter violation resulting from delay of the Pay Equity  
Agreement’s implementation is justifiable under s. 1 from the standpoint of  
the legislative objective’s importance, and of the measure’s rational  
connection and minimal impairment, the measure’s deleterious impact  
remains to be addressed to determine whether that effect nonetheless  
outweighs the measure’s objective. This is the last stage of the s. 1 analysis,  
and will bring to a close not only this judgment’s consideration of the three  
components of the proportionality test, but also its treatment of the  
constitutional issues encountered in this appeal.  
Page: 176  
[477] The following passage from pp. 139-140 of Dickson C.J.C.’s judgment in  
Oakes explains the essential nature of the inquiry into this third and final  
component of the proportionality test:  
C
Some limits on rights and freedoms protected by the Charter will be  
more serious than others in terms of the nature of the right or freedom  
violated, the extent of the violation, and the degree to which the  
measures which impose the limit trench upon the integral principles  
of a free and democratic society. Even if an objective is of sufficient  
importance, and the first two elements of the proportionality test are  
satisfied, it is still possible that, because of the severity of the  
deleterious effects of a measure on individuals or groups, the measure  
will not be justified by the purposes it is intended to serve. The more  
severe the deleterious effects of a measure, the more important the  
objective must be if the measure is to be reasonable and demonstrably  
justified in a free and democratic society.  
[478] As earlier observed in preceding para. 361, this final component of  
proportionality, requiring comparative analysis of the impugned limitation’s  
deleterious effects with the salutary impact of its objective, arguably may be  
regarded as lying at the nub of the delicate balance between individual  
rights and communal needs required to be struck under s. 1. Having  
established the sufficiency of the legislative objective’s importance and the  
first two components of the proportionality test, justification of the  
limitation now receives a final screening through inquiry into whether the  
measure’s effects are, nonetheless, disproportionate to its purpose. If found  
disproportional, the constitutional limitation cannot be held justifiable under  
s. 1 as the deleterious effects will have to be deemed too high a cost to bear  
in attaining the objective which the infringing measure is intended to attain.  
This final screening process into disproportionate deleterious effects can be  
seen as akin to surveys of prejudicial effects upon which admissibility of  
certain categories of evidence frequently will ultimately hinge.  
*
preceding determinations:  
[479] As was the case with minimal impairment, the arbitration decision that the  
limitation measure had a disproportionate deleterious effect, counteracting  
the salutary effect of its objective, was the product of a majority decision  
formed as a result of the union nominee’s blanket endorsation of the  
Chairperson’s analysis of the Charter’s application to the circumstances  
Page: 177  
obtaining. As preceding para. 34 records, the Chairperson had concluded  
the infringement perpetrated by the legislative measure was “too high a  
price to pay”. Accordingly, the consequential violation effected by  
extending the systemic discrimination over the restraint period was deemed  
by the majority to exact a disproportionate price vis à vis the benefit of the  
legislative objective of addressing the threat to the provincial economy  
which looming fiscal deficits presented.  
[480] As he had in his assessment of the minimal impairment component,  
Government’s nominee departed from the majority view of disproportionate  
effect. Influenced by the three factors recounted in preceding para. 48, he  
concluded the restraint measure had struck a reasonable balance with its  
legislative objective of combatting the economic threat, and accordingly met  
the requirement of proportionate effect.  
[481] The judge did not side with the majority view, but concluded the violation  
of the affected employees’ s. 15(1) equality rights by the impugned restraint  
measure was not “too high a price to pay” to achieve its objective of  
containing and reducing the fiscal deficitary situation confronting the  
Province. As preceding paras. 83 and 84 recount, while not discounting the  
adverse impact of the postponement of pay equity, particularly on those  
retirees leaving the work force during the period of the postponement, who  
otherwise would have had the benefits the pay equity’s implementation  
reflected in future pension cheques, the judge, nonetheless, held “the law  
did not have a disproportionality severe effect ...”. As she had challenged  
the minimal impairment finding, NAPE’s counsel also takes issue with this  
holding of the judge.  
*
positions of counsel:  
[482] Counsel for NAPE opens her disproportionate effects submissions by  
stressing the nature and import of the rights affected, whilst underscoring  
the extent of the prejudice visited on those whose rights were limited by the  
pay equity postponement perpetrated through s. 9 of the restraint legislation.  
From that standpoint she insists it untenable to maintain the cost of keeping  
the promise of pay equity to women was not affordable, and had to be  
deferred, albeit temporarily, to other financial priorities, even in times of  
serious economic deteriorations.  
[483] Claiming support from cases which will be treated in the ensuing discussion  
of the respective positions of counsel in this appeal, NAPE’s counsel rejects  
Page: 178  
the notions that the limiting measure at bar may be rationalized by claims of  
the need of governmental incrementalism in face of the economic crisis that  
loomed; or, by dismissing that legislative action as a mere putting off to  
another day realization of the pay equity promises by adjusting the approach  
to their fulfillment. In this regard, counsel argues the impugned legislative  
measure fails to deal with the permanent deleterious effects on retired  
women and those falling eligible for workers’ compensation benefits within  
the restraint periods. Unless the arbitration award is upheld, she goes on to  
insist, those women will never realize the benefit of the pay equity promises  
made at the end of their active membership in the workforce. For them, she  
maintains, the discrimination will be very significant as it will continue in  
perpetuity, freezing their pensions and compensation at rates referable to the  
systemic discrimination that Government had undertaken to end. This, she  
describes as a “devastating effect” foreclosing any pretense of  
proportionality.  
[484] Apparently content to leave his answer to his counterpart’s stress on the  
nature and import of the affected equality rights to his submissions on the  
relatively superior importance of the legislative objective advanced in his  
argument on the first of the Oakes criteria, counsel for Government centers  
his rejoinder on the aspects of opposing counsel’s arguments that focused  
on the incrementalism and prejudice to employees who had left the  
workforce during the restraints. Thus, he responds to that focus with  
judicial authority of his own, whilst contending there is nothing untoward in  
governments taking incremental approaches to resolutions of constitutional  
problems. Insofar as the effect upon retirees and those who found  
themselves on workers compensation during the restraint periods, he  
answers that the pay equity promises under the Agreement incorporated into  
the Collective Agreement call for an incremental approach to its  
implementation.  
[485] The appraisal of these positions will be conducted in three steps. Firstly, the  
arguments of NAPE’s counsel based on the nature of the affected rights and  
their importance will be discussed. This will be followed by consideration  
of the incrementalism argument. The appraisal will conclude with  
evaluation of the argument addressing the continuing effects upon retirees  
and employees in receipt of worker compensation benefits.  
*
nature and importance of rights:  
Page: 179  
[486] In furtherance of her argument’s accentuation of the nature and importance  
of the infringed equality rights, counsel for NAPE enlists the 1984 Abella  
Royal Commission Report on Equality in Employment to buttress  
counsel’s portrayal as “staggering and unjustifiable” the violation of female  
employees’ constitutional equality rights perpetrated by the postponement  
of pay equity in the circumstances at bar. To this end, she highlights the  
following passage from p. 235 of that Report:  
C
The cost of the wage gap to women is staggering. And the sacrifice is  
not in aid of any demonstrably justifiable social goal. To argue, as  
some have, that we cannot afford the cost of equal pay to women is to  
imply that women somehow have a duty to be paid less until other  
financial priorities are accommodated. This reasoning is specious and  
it is based on an unacceptable premise that the acceptance of arbitrary  
distinctions based on gender is a legitimate basis for imposing  
negative consequences, particularly when the economy is faltering.  
[487] Traces of counsel’s submissions on the sufficiency of the restraint  
legislation’s importance for justification under s. 1 of the legislative  
objective’s importance can be discerned from her reliance on the foregoing  
passage for the Abella Report. This is inevitable to a degree, of course,  
inasmuch as the established importance of the restraint legislation’s  
objective is paired with the measure adopted in this final rescreening phase  
in testing the proportionality of the deleterious effects. As already noted in  
preceding para. 434, focus of all components of the proportionality test  
under s. 1 is upon the measure invoked to achieve the objective. However,  
while the final phase’s concentration, centering on whether the prejudicial  
effect of the measure’s deferral of enjoyment of pay equity outweighs the  
established importance of the restraint legislation’s purpose of combatting  
the serious threat to the economy, also requires advertence to the legislative  
objective’s significance, the process does not involve a rehashing of the  
settled importance of the measure’s objective.  
[488] By the same token, it needs also be underscored that neither does the  
conduct of that process allow any gainsaying or discounting of the  
importance of the equality rights affected by deferral of the pay equity  
compensation. Indeed, in keeping with the direction conveyed in the  
passage from Oakes reproduced in preceding para. 477, this inquiry into the  
third and final component of the proportionality test proceeds on the footing  
that the infringement of the equality rights at bar ranks amongst the “more  
Page: 180  
serious” of the “limits on rights and freedoms protected by the Charter”.  
Accordingly, following that instruction in Oakes, the inquiry will proceed  
on the basis that the measure’s infringement must be placed amongst the  
“more severe” so that “the more important the objective must be if the  
measure is to be [held] reasonable and demonstrably justified in a free and  
democratic society” under s. 1 of the Charter.  
[489] No exception is taken with the accentuation, placed by counsel for NAPE  
and the Abella Report enlisted by her, on the nature and importance of pay  
equity for women. It follows that the seriousness of the deleterious effects  
of the limitation placed by the restraint legislation upon the promised pay  
equity’s enjoyment is beyond question. However, enjoyment of  
constitutionally protected rights is not absolute. While the very severe  
deleterious effects of the limiting measure indubitably will weigh heavily on  
one side of the scales of s. 1 justification, its legislative objective of  
containing and reducing the threat of escalating deficits, described to the  
House of Assembly by the Minister of Finance in his “extended budgetary  
explanation” as hovering over the Province must be placed on the other.  
Accordingly, this judgment fully endorses the accentuation placed by  
counsel, and the Abella Report enlisted by her, on the importance of pay  
equity, as well as the consequential severity of the abridgement of those  
rights. However, with due respect, it does not share the apparent thesis that  
that importance and severity is such that it eclipses any consideration of  
justification of limitations placed on those rights in order to contain and  
reduce serious fiscal deficits of the magnitude forecasted by the Minister.  
[490] This jurisdiction knows full well from its own history the danger which  
mushrooming fiscal deficits of the magnitude forecasted can pose to the  
very existence of democratically elected government. All one needs do to  
gain a full appreciation of the reality and seriousness of that risk is to peruse  
the Report of the Royal Commission established on February 17, 1933, to  
examine Newfoundland’s future in light of its then subsisting “financial  
situation and prospects”. Named after its chairperson, the Commission’s  
Amulree Report, citing in para. 634 Newfoundland’s “extreme financial  
difficulties” consequential upon “the present burden of the public debt ...  
wholly beyond the country’s capacity”, made as its principal  
recommendation in para. 634(4) that:  
C
... the Newfoundland Government, recognizing that it is impossible  
for the Island to surmount unaided the unprecedented difficulties that  
Page: 181  
now confront it, should make an immediate appeal for the  
sympathetic co-operation of Your Majesty’s Government in the  
United Kingdom in the adoption and execution of a joint plan of  
reconstruction of which the following would be the main features:-  
(a) The existing form of government would be suspended until  
such time as the Island may become self-supporting again.  
(b) A special Commission of Government would be created  
which would be presided over by His Excellency the Governor,  
would be vested with full legislative and executive authority,  
and would take the place of the existing Legislative and  
Executive Council.  
C
C
C
(c) The Commission of Government would be composed of six  
members, exclusive of the Governor, three of whom would be  
drawn from Newfoundland and three from the United  
Kingdom.  
[491] There were five other features of the Amulree’s Report’s “Main  
Recommendation”. They dealt with the organization of the Departments of  
Government under the proposed commission; a statement that the  
“proceedings of the Commission of Government would be subject to  
supervisory control by Your Majesty’s Government in the United  
Kingdom”; the United Kingdom’s assumption of “general responsibility for  
the finances of the Island until such time as it may become self-supporting  
again” at which time “responsible government, on request from the people  
of Newfoundland, would be restored”; and, suggestions on appropriate  
procedures for bringing Amulree’s main recommendation into effect.  
These other features were subsidiary to the principal one proposing the  
temporary surrender of self-government. Clearly, it was the yoke of its  
deficitary burden that constrained Newfoundland to accept the Amulree  
Report’s proposal of suspension of democratically elected responsible  
government against the day of its restoration on the “Island” becoming  
“self-supporting again”.  
[492] Any illusion of overstatement in the comparison being drawn between the  
threatened consequences projected here from the “horrendous” soaring  
deficits outlined in the speech of March 19, 1991, by the Minister of  
Finance to the Legislature, and the burden of the past indebtedness detailed  
in the Amulree Report which harbingered the loss of self-government, can  
be readily dispelled on comparative perusals of 1991 ministerial “extended  
Page: 182  
budgetary explanation” and the budget speech delivered on June 29, 1933,  
in the House of Assembly, which was published as appendix J to the  
Amulree Report. The 1933 speech was made by Newfoundland’s Prime  
Minister, Hon. F.C. Alderdice, who also held the finance portfolio. It was  
delivered some three months prior to completion of the work of the  
Amulree Commission to which it referred at the outset (see p. 260 of the  
Report) as then being in the process of:  
C
... studying thoroughly and sympathetically our local conditions and  
our financial and business prospects with a view to advising the  
Dominion as to the most satisfactory solution for meeting its present  
difficulties, and as to the most effective use which it can make of its  
immense potential resources.  
[493] The outline given in the Alderdice administration budget speech of the  
economic situation then prevailing provides chilling witness to the  
consequences of unchecked spiralling governmental deficits. Thus, it  
reported cuts in projected expenditures in the preceding year in education,  
health, welfare, war pensions and civil service salaries and pensions. (See  
p. 262 of the Amulree Report). These “economies” were not surprisingly  
described as “drastic” considering the relative size of the budget for the  
1932-33 fiscal year. Indeed, the Prime Minister’s description of those cuts  
as “producing considerable hardship”might be taken as rank  
understatement. While the 1933 budget speech tended to attribute, not  
without some justification, the cause of the faltering economy to depressed  
economic conditions which had spread over nearly every country in the  
world, the Amulree Report leaves no room to doubt that the local fiscal  
situation was exacerbated in no small part by the public debt burden that  
had accumulated over the years.  
[494] It is not being suggested here that the deficitary position described nearly  
sixty years later in the ministerial “extended budgetary explanation” was of  
such catastrophic moment as to herald another Commission of Government,  
even though it must be said that such a consequence of the public  
borrowings which had preceded the 1933 budget must be assumed to have  
been beyond the contemplation of preceding governments incurring them.  
It is not too great a quantum leap, however, to suggest, just as had the  
deficitary burden some sixty years earlier, the deficits which preceding para.  
414 notes the Minister of Finance forecasted in 1991, if unaddressed, would  
have had to have a very serious deleterious effect upon the Province’s  
Page: 183  
ability to provide basic health, educational and social services, as well as  
precipitating potential deep general public service salary and pension cuts.  
It is impossible to contemplate the Province being saddled with deficitary  
burdens to the tune of $400 to $600 million annually without it being  
thrown into the severest of economic crises, requiring deepening cuts into  
those areas which manifestly secure those “other values and principles of a  
free and democratic society”, of which the quote from M v. H in preceding  
para. 379 speaks. On the basis of the reasoning already developed in paras.  
379 to 420, whilst giving fullest expression to the nature and importance of  
the individual equality rights affected by the deferral of pay equity  
entitlements in this case, the enjoyment of them would, in the words of  
Oakes at p. 136, nonetheless “be inimical to the realization of collective  
goals of fundamental importance”, in light of the “horrendous” soaring  
deficits, and the clear threat they posed to those “other values and principles  
of a free and democratic society”.  
[495] For the foregoing reasons, then, this judgment rejects the argument  
accentuating the nature and importance of the affected pay equity equality  
rights as a basis for holding the deleterious effects of the limiting restraint  
measure render the consequential Charter infringement unjustifiable under  
s. 1. With due respect, the submission smacks of absolutism, which is not  
the standard of enjoyment of fundamental rights and freedoms which the  
Charter imported into the Canadian Constitution. It was open to the trial  
judge, without in any way denigrating the nature and importance of the  
infringed equality rights, to have yet concluded the overlooked “extended  
budgetary explanation given by the Minister”, which outlined the  
imperative of containing and reducing fiscal deficits seriously threatening  
the Province’s economic security and well-being, established the severity of  
the deleterious effects of the measure at bar that postponed enjoyment of the  
promised pay equity, to be justified by the urgent purposes of containing  
and reducing looming deficits which the measure was intended to serve.  
[496] Having disposed thusly of the first argument on the proportionality of  
effects advanced by NAPE, attention will now focus on incrementalism.  
Page: 184  
*
the incrementalism argument:  
[497] But for the case law enlisted in support of it, the incrementalism submission  
put forth by NAPE’s counsel might be dismissed as tantamount to a  
recasting of the argument just rejected which accentuated the nature and  
importance of the infringed s. 15(1)equality rights. This is because it is  
constructed on the notion that the provision of the promised pay equity is  
such a fundamentally important right that its deferral may not be  
rationalized or dismissed by camping on the fact that the limiting measure  
did not constitute a total ban, but merely postponed reparation of the pay  
equity discrimination. If this were the essential gist of the submission,  
without more, it could be summarily rejected for the same reasons of  
paramountcy of the measure’s objective of containing and reducing the  
forecasted serious escalating deficits. However, there is another arrow to  
counsel’s bow in this argument. It lies in her claim that her position on  
incrementalism is supported by case law.  
[498] The first of the cases upon which counsel relies is Service Employees  
International which resurfaces for the third time in this judgment, having  
been enlisted by counsel for Government in his jurisdictional submissions,  
and again by him in his challenge of the trial judge’s upholding of the  
Arbitration Board’s Charter violation finding. Here, it is being enlisted by  
counsel for NAPE in support of her contention that the weight of authority  
disapproves of incrementalism as appropriate justification for Charter  
violations. Thus, she highlights the following passage from Service  
Employees International where, in addressing the amendment to the pay  
equity legislation under consideration in that case, O’Leary J. stated at p.  
535:  
C
It must also be noted that the Schedule J amendment cannot be  
justified as an incremental approach to pay equity. It is not a matter  
of putting off to another day, when the same can be afforded, the  
correction of the gender-based systemic wage inequity from which  
women in the proxy sector undoubtedly suffer. Schedule J and the  
government’s position on this application tells proxy sector women  
they are not and cannot be covered under the Pay Equity Act even  
though other women in the broader public sector have had their  
systemic gender-based wage inequity 100 per cent cured.  
[499] This passage, however, may not be enlisted to assist the incrementalism  
argument being advanced by counsel for NAPE. This is because the  
Page: 185  
amendment to the pay equity undertaking in Service Employees  
International was a measure distinguishable from the one under scrutiny at  
bar. Hence, as preceding paras. 143 and 292 have already pointed out, the  
measure under consideration in Service Employees International  
substantially eliminated pay equity adjustments for almost all unionized  
women in the public service, but not all of them. Thus, the legislative  
measure created discriminatory constitutional inequality on its own. In  
contrast, the impugned restraint measure at bar did not eliminate pay equity  
for most, and not all, but rather was a blanket across-the-board  
postponement of the promised reparation of the long-standing “systemic  
gender-based wage inequity”. It applied to all unionized employees,  
perpetrating no discrimination of its own.  
[500] The second case relied on for support by counsel for NAPE is Vriend v.  
Alberta, [1998] 1 S.C.R. 493. This case involved the termination of  
employment of a member of a college’s staff, who had disclosed he was a  
homosexual, on grounds of the college’s policy with respect to such  
practice. The majority of the Court held the consequential infringement of  
the dismissed employee’s s. 15(1) Charter equality rights was not  
justifiable under s. 1, and read into the Province’s human rights legislation  
“sexual orientation” as a prohibited ground of discrimination. Of immediate  
relevance to the incrementalism argument of NAPE’s counsel is para. 122 of  
the majority judgment in Vriend where Mr. Justice Iacobucci, in the  
majority’s disposition that he jointly authored with Cory J., stated as  
follows:  
C
In addition, in Egan, writing on behalf of myself and Cory J., I  
took the position that the need for governmental incrementalism was  
an inappropriate justification for Charter violations. I remain  
convinced that this approach is generally not suitable for that  
purpose, especially where, as here, the statute in issue is a  
comprehensive code of human rights provisions. In my opinion,  
groups that have historically been the target of discrimination cannot  
be expected to wait patiently for the protection of their human dignity  
and equal rights while governments move toward reform one step at a  
time. If the infringement of the rights and freedoms of these groups is  
permitted to persist while governments fail to pursue equality  
diligently, then the guarantees of the Charter will be reduced to little  
more than empty words.  
Page: 186  
[501] The last case co-opted by NAPE’s counsel to her incrementalism argument  
is M. v. H. That case decided the denial of parties to same-sex relationships  
to relief under family law legislation infringed s. 15(1) equality rights and  
the violation was unjustifiable under s. 1 of the Charter. Counsel enlists  
the following portion written by Iacobucci J. in the majority judgment that  
he also co-authored with Cory J., where the former stated in para. 128:  
C
... As this Court noted in Vriend, supra, governmental  
incrementalism, or the notion that government ought to be accorded  
time to amend discriminatory legislation, is generally an inappropriate  
justification for Charter violations. However, even if I were to accept  
that such a justification might be suitable in the present case, it seems  
to me that its application to the facts of the case at bar cannot  
legitimize the continued exclusion of same-sex couples from the  
FLA’s spousal support regime.  
[502] With due respect, none of these three cases assist counsel’s premise that the  
weight of authority disapproves of incrementalism in the circumstances of  
this case as appropriate justification for violation of the affected equality  
rights. Taking “incrementalism”, as does the preceding excerpt from M. v.  
H., to mean reparation of discrimination over time, it is noted that all three  
of the foregoing cases, on which counsel rests her argument that  
incrementalism cannot justify the postponement, were addressing  
governmental actions that excluded individuals from exercising rights  
enjoyable by others. Hence, in M. v. H. the s. 15(1) Charter discrimination  
held inappropriately justifiable on the argument that it was repairable over  
time was perpetrated by the legislative exclusion of same-sex couples from  
rights under the spousal support regime of the family law legislation that  
had been extended in the statute to unmarried opposite-sex couples. In  
Vriend, the discrimination unjustifiable by incrementalism was ultimately  
traceable to governmental omission of “sex orientation” in the human rights  
legislation which would have excluded the affected employee from  
employment enjoyable by heterosexual employees, if it had not been  
effectively judicially amended as it was in Vriend. In Service Employees  
International the discrimination likewise held unjustifiable was visited  
upon employees excluded from pay equity entitlement through repeal of the  
legislated comparative proxy method, whilst others continued to enjoy that  
right.  
Page: 187  
[503] In contrast, the governmental legislative action at bar did not  
discriminatorily exclude some from pay equity, whilst leaving enjoyment to  
others of those constitutionally protected rights. By its terms, the restraint  
legislation applied to all pay equity agreements concluded within the public  
sector. There was no evidence that other unionized employees in the public  
sector had gained pay equity through the collective bargaining process. In  
fact, as already mentioned at the outset of this judgment, NAPE had  
regarded the conclusion of the Pay Equity Agreement of June 24, 1988, and  
its addition as schedules to six subsisting collective agreements, as  
reparation of a long-standing injustice within the public sector. Considered  
from that perspective, its subsequent postponement through the impugned  
legislation was the source of its understandable frustration.  
[504] The legislative postponement, therefore, could not be viewed as temporarily  
excluding affected employees from their s. 15(1) equality rights whilst  
similar rights were being enjoyed by others. There was nothing selective  
about the restraints on pay equity, either in the legislation’s terms or its  
implementation. It was an across-the-board deferral which caught everyone  
entitled to pay equity. Therein lies the distinction between this case and the  
three enlisted by counsel.  
[505] Moreover, the incrementalism that is mooted in justification of the  
legislative measure’s rights infringement at bar can be seen as one of  
inclusion, rather than exclusion. Thus, as preceding para. 99 recounts, and  
this judgment will subsequently endorse, the trial judge concluded the  
language of the legislative restraint provision should be read in the context  
of the Pay Equity Agreement; and observed that, in so doing, it can be seen  
that each contemplates “an incremental approach to the achievement of pay  
equity”. From this standpoint the judge went on to reason the effect of that  
provision’s s-s. 9(3) “was to replace April 1, 1988, being the first pay equity  
adjustment date prescribed under the Agreement”, leaving that Agreement  
otherwise unaffected. From the standpoint of this reasoning, the judge  
construed the effect of that provision of the violative legislative restraint  
measure to be the continuance of the pay equity adjustments in the same  
incremental progression as they were payable under the Agreement, but  
commencing after the expiry of the restraint period, with full entitlement  
being incrementally realizable “within the five year period” provided in the  
Agreement.  
Page: 188  
[506] Accepting this construction by the trial judge, it is apparent that the  
incrementalism encountered in this case, either in the Pay Equity Agreement  
itself or in its postponement under the restraint legislation, does not entail  
the need to rationalize excluding some from pay equity, whilst justifying  
that action, in the words of the excerpt from M. v. H. in preceding para.  
501, on “the notion that government ought to be accorded time to amend  
discriminatory legislation”. It is rather an incrementalism that includes pay  
equity for all through graduated payments of incremental payments over a  
prescribed time. To resort to useful concrete analogy, it is not an  
incrementalism that would see some vessels completely empty awaiting to  
be filled, whilst others were filled to the brim. It rather envisages empty  
vessels being filled in graduated progression until all are filled to their rims  
at the same time.  
[507] Government’s counsel puts forth an authority of his own to counter the three  
cases cited by opposing counsel in support of her incrementalism argument.  
Thus, he appropriates for that purpose the following passage from p. 317 of  
La Forest J.’s lead majority judgment in McKinney:  
C
In looking at this type of issue, it is important to remember that a  
Legislature should not be obliged to deal with all aspects of a  
problem at once. It must surely be permitted to take incremental  
measures. It must be given reasonable leeway to deal with problems  
one step at a time, to balance possible inequalities under the law  
against other inequalities resulting from the adoption of a course of  
action, and to take account of the difficulties, whether social,  
economic or budgetary, that would arise if it attempted to deal with  
social and economic problems in their entirety, assuming such  
problems can ever be perceived in their entirety. This Court has had  
occasion to advert to possibilities of this kind.  
[508] Counsel uses this passage as authority to buttress his submission that  
governments are entitled “to take incremental measures” in resolving  
discriminations that violate s. 15(1) equality rights. In effect, he is  
contending Government in the case at bar merely exercised its justifiable  
“reasonable leeway” in postponing the promised five year phase-in period  
for implementation of pay equity in order to address the critical deficitary  
situation confronting the Province at that time. He is relying on the  
foregoing extract from McKinney, therefore, in rebuttal of opposing  
counsel’s authorities, which she proffers in support of her challenge of  
Page: 189  
incrementalism being used to rationalize dismissal of the impugned measure  
as merely putting off pay equity’s realization on the same incremental step  
by step basis as originally provided under the Pay Equity Agreement to  
another day.  
[509] As to this appropriation of McKinney by Government in response to the  
authorities put forth by NAPE, it has to be acknowledged that its application  
as a general proposition in the circumstances at bar is not altogether  
unproblematic. The problem with its application here is signalled in its  
opening words which indicate the passage’s addressing “this type of issue”.  
Hence the “leeway” not to have to tackle “all aspects of a problem at once”  
must be considered in the context of the “type of issue” to which the latitude  
“to take incremental measures” referred. In McKinney the “type of issue”  
is quite different from that presented at bar. That case involved challenges  
to mandatory retirement policies by university employees who had passed  
their sixty-fifth birthdays. The issue in McKinney was the Charter  
compatibility of a provision of Ontario’s Human Rights Code, 1981, S.O.  
c. 53 which restricted the right to equal treatment in employment without  
discrimination because of age to those less than sixty-five. Whilst  
upholding the policies on other grounds, the majority in McKinney agreed  
the Code’s provision violated s. 15(1) Charter equality rights, but held it  
nonetheless justifiable under s. 1 as a reasonable limit on those guaranteed  
rights.  
[510] As may be seen from this backdrop to McKinney, the Charter  
compatibility issue raised in that case was of the type that addressed alleged  
exclusion of employees over sixty-five from equal protection and benefit of  
the law without discrimination in their employment based on age, in  
contravention of s. 15(1) of the Charter, which protection and benefit had  
been extended to employees who had not yet celebrated their sixty-fifth  
birthdays. As was the situation with the three cases put forth by NAPE,  
then, Government’s counsel is resting his argument, in rebuttal of NAPE’s  
contention that no case law exists supporting incrementalism as appropriate  
justification for Charter violations, on authority that also had addressed the  
s. 15(1) Charter compatibility of governmental measures in the context of  
legislation that excluded some individuals from exercising constitutionally  
protected rights enjoyed by others. Continuing with the analogy to empty  
and full vessels made in preceding para. 505, all four cases may be  
visualized as comprehending situations where some vessels are left  
Page: 190  
completely empty, awaiting to be filled, whilst others have been entirely  
filled.  
[511] With McKinney raising the same type of discriminatory issue of exclusion  
from constitutional protection which was enjoyed by others, it, too, is  
distinguishable from the situation at bar where the issue of justifiable  
discrimination arises, not as a result of the exclusion of some from their  
equality rights, but rather because of legislated postponement of promised  
incremental phase-in of across-the-board exclusion of these rights. Being so  
distinguishable, it would appear, solely on that account, that McKinney  
would no more assist Government’s stance that it provides authoritative  
support for incrementalism as appropriate justification for the Charter  
violation perpetrated through the limitation on the pay equity enjoyment by  
the impugned restraint legislation, than the three cases submitted by NAPE  
serve as authority for inexorable dismissals of incrementalism as  
inappropriate justifications of Charter violations.  
[512] Whilst discounting McKinney as an authority in that respect, it nonetheless  
has utility in this discussion of the proportionate effects of the impugned  
legislative restraint measure. Its value lies in its direction that the focus of  
analyses of that component of the proportionality test should be  
circumstantially oriented. Viewed in the context of the circumstances at  
bar, that direction assists the conclusion that incrementalism is actually  
irrelevant to the proportionate effects inquiry being conducted here. This is  
because those circumstances show the postponement of implementation of  
the agreed pay equity process to be the catalyst of the restraint measures  
deleterious effects, and not the process’ incremental format of  
implementation which had neutral impact.  
[513] The direction assisting the conclusion that the deleterious effects flow from  
the postponement can be found in the paragraph in McKinney immediately  
preceding the highlighted excerpt reproduced in preceding para. 507.  
There, LaForest J. admonishes courts to “to exercise considerable caution”  
in addressing the proportionate effects component of the proportionality  
test, whilst indicating that particular heed should be paid to the situation  
leading to the original governmental decision that the measure’s objective  
warranted its rights’ limitation. The salient circumstance, which LaForest J.  
saw as affording a basis for his holding in McKinney that the measure’s  
objective outweighed its deleterious effect of excluding employees over  
sixty-five from constitutional protection against mandatory retirement, was  
Page: 191  
that the Legislature, in enacting the measure in the Ontario Human Rights  
Code:  
C
... sought to provide protection for a group which it perceived to be  
most in need and did not include others for rational and serious  
considerations that, it had reasonable grounds to believe, would  
seriously affect the rights of others.  
[514] Vriend’s and M. v. H.’s subsequent assertions that governmental  
incrementalism is inappropriate justification for Charter violations should  
not be seen at odds with McKinney’s holding in the excerpt reproduced in  
preceding para. 507 that Legislatures are entitled to “take incremental  
measures” in addressing the proportional effects component of justification  
of such violations. As Iacobucci J. went on to observe in M. v. H., the  
incrementalism notion is “generally” inappropriate. Thus McKinney,  
Vriend and M. v. H. can be consistently read together by reasonably  
regarding McKinney’s holding that the incremental inclusion of some  
within the ambit of legislative protection from mandatory retirement  
because of age, whilst excluding others, was appropriately justifiable in the  
circumstances obtaining as an exception to the general rule.  
[515] McKinney’s value, then, lies not in transposability as a general proposition  
of endorsation of governmental incrementalism as appropriate justification  
for Charter violations in contradistinction to Vriend and M. v. H. Its  
relevance to the circumstances at bar lies in its direction to have careful  
regard to the factual matrix arising from those circumstances in conducting  
analyses of proportionality of effects, and “to exercise considerable caution”  
in doing so. In heeding that cautionary note, it can be seen from the  
circumstances at bar that the deleterious effect of the impugned restraint  
measure stems not from the incremental payments through which the  
promised pay equity was to be achieved under both the Pay Equity  
Agreement and the restraint legislation that deferred its implementation, but  
rather from the postponement of those payments.  
[516] Thus, the evidence establishes the parties originally agreed that pay equity  
would be implemented in five incremental annual steps through budgetary  
votes capped at 1% of the preceding year’s payroll for the health care sector  
during the first four years, with any remainder necessary to full attainment  
being payable in the fifth year. Moreover, the authorities agree, and the  
arguments of counsel show, it was common ground that Government had no  
obligation to act to address systemic gender discrimination in employment.  
Page: 192  
It follows that in electing to do so, apart altogether from the fact that the  
incremental procedure was mutually agreed by the parties, Government was  
entitled to proceed initially via the incremental process provided under the  
Pay Equity Agreement. This it did through its executive arm when the  
Agreement was concluded and became “law”.  
[517] However, once that process was in place Government was not at liberty to  
renege on its promise without laying itself open to sustainable claims of  
violation of the equality rights of those affected. As the trial judge held in  
adopting the excerpt from the decision of the Board’s chairperson which is  
reproduced in preceding para. 74, once Government agreed to that process,  
it could not resile from it without violating s. 15(1) equality rights. This is  
because the denial of pay equity as promised no longer was attributable to  
systemic gender discrimination, but stemmed from governmental action.  
Since the limitation was not systemic, but a product of governmental action  
by its legislative branch, the starting point in addressing the proportionate  
effects component of the proportionality test in the context of the studied  
cautionary note sounded in McKinney would logically be to determine  
what the circumstances show to have constituted the limiting legislative  
action.  
[518] The most salient circumstance that immediately springs to the fore in  
broaching that inquiry is that the impugned restraint legislation wrought  
essentially no change in the sense of remodelling or remoulding the  
incremental method by which Government initially agreed, and was then  
free to adopt, in stamping out the systemic gender discrimination of pay  
inequity between female and male dominated classes of employees. Thus,  
the incremental process as agreed by Government, and given the force of  
“law” by its executive branch through the appendage of that Agreement to  
the Collective Agreements, remained fundamentally intact in the restraint  
legislation. Accordingly, the promised pay equity continued to be realizable  
by adjustments spread over five years through incremental payments equal  
to 1% of payroll over the first four years from the expiry of the restraint  
period, with the remainder necessary to achieve full pay equity being  
payable in the fifth year after expiry of the legislated restraint period. The  
only change in the promised process of implementation of pay equity  
effectuated by the restraint measure lay in its three year postponement of its  
scheduled phase-in commencement date of April 1, 1988. This being so,  
there was no arguable deleterious effect in the governmental incrementalism  
Page: 193  
process continued in the restraint legislation, and counsel’s argument  
founded on incrementalism can be dismissed on that account. Instead,  
attention should be focussed on the effect of the process’ postponement.  
[519] In addressing the effect of that postponement, it is important to recognize  
that the impact of that legislative action upon one group of affected  
employees was not entirely the same as was its consequence to another  
identifiable group. The first group is comprised of employees who would  
have worked within the bargaining units, to whose Collective Agreements  
the Pay Equity Agreement had been appended, at any time within the eight  
year time frame spanning April 1, 1988 to March 31, 1996, without retiring  
on pensions or workers compensation benefits. That time frame covers the  
three year period of the restraint measure during which the scheduled  
commencement of pay equity adjustments was postponed, and the ensuing  
five years to which the phase-in of the promised entitlements was deferred.  
[520] In contrast, the second group encompasses those amongst the employees of  
the same bargaining units who retired within that eight year time frame on  
pension or those benefits. While the real deleterious effect visited on both  
groups by the restraint measure was attributable to the postponement of the  
incremental process for the achievement of pay equity it effectuated, as will  
presently be explained, from an entirely materialistic perspective, the harm  
it perpetrated had greater consequences for the second group than the first.  
[521] The effect on the first group, from a purely monetary standpoint, would  
have been confined to straight salary loss. Over the time frame’s first three  
years the loss would be measurable by the lack of inclusion of the promised  
pay equity adjustments in salary cheques. In the fourth year the loss would  
be less because, by then, the restraint period would have expired and pay  
equity would have commenced with a legislative budgetary vote of 1% of  
payroll, which is what employees would have received in that same year  
under the Pay Equity Agreement. There would still have been some  
deleterious effect in the fourth year, nonetheless, inasmuch as the previous  
year’s payroll on which the 1% incremental was calculable would not have  
included the increases in the payroll that would have incrementally  
accumulated in prior years under the Agreement. Losses would have been  
higher in the fifth to seventh years, however, because employees would only  
be receiving increments provided through the 1% of payroll formula rather  
than full pay equity that would have been payable under the Agreement.  
Only in the eight year would the deferred pay equity implementation catch  
Page: 194  
up with the originally scheduled phase-in of it, with the fifth year’s shift to  
the eighth year in which full pay equity would then have been achieved.  
[522] This, then, is the measurable deleterious effect, from a purely monetary  
point of view, perpetrated on affected employees who were impacted by the  
restraint measure, and who did not retire to draw pensions or workers  
compensation benefits during the eight year time frame of the  
postponement’s impact. In defining the effect in that light, it is fully  
appreciated that the deleterious consequences transcended material  
concerns. Thus, apart from its monetary impact, the measure can be seen as  
having the effect of constraining affected employees to work longer in  
circumstances tending to engender feelings that the value of their  
contributions was esteemed less on the speciously irrelevant ground of  
gender. As has been underscored periodically throughout this judgment,  
that aspect of the sense of harm attributable to this longstanding injustice is  
understandably keenly felt by NAPE, and caused it to look on the deferral of  
its reparation as a rankly unjustifiable prejudice upon women from both  
groups.  
[523] This judgment fully appreciates those feelings, and does not discount the  
depth and seriousness of the deleterious effects, both material and  
otherwise, of the postponement of the attainment of those equality rights.  
Nevertheless, agreement must be lent to the view that the deleterious effects  
of the limitation of those constitutionally protected rights through the  
postponement of the agreed incremental pay equity process upon employees  
falling within the first group is outweighed by the restraint measure’s  
pressing and substantial objective of containing and reducing the forecasted  
budgetary deficits. The ominous and dire consequences for the Province’s  
capacity to provide, in the words of M. v. H. quoted in preceding para. 379,  
those “other values and principles of a free and democratic society”, which  
consequences the escalating deficits forecasted in the overlooked  
“budgetary explanation” unmistakeably foreboded, afford sufficient reason  
for the trial judge to have paid deference to the implicit legislative  
determination that pressing and substantial societal considerations  
justifiably outweighed the restraint measure’s deleterious impact upon the  
affected individual equality rights. Accordingly, this judgment sides with  
the trial judge’s conclusion that the impugned measure was not “too high a  
price to pay”, insofar as the first group is concerned; and, that the  
Page: 195  
Arbitration Board’s majority erred in overlooking “the extended budgetary  
explanation given by the Minister” in finding to the contrary.  
[524] As will be apparent from a perusal of his reasoning dealing with the  
proportionality of effects, recounted in the extract from his decision  
reproduced in preceding para. 84, the judge made no differentiation  
regarding the measure’s effect on affected employees. Hence, his finding  
that the measure’s rights limitation was not “too high a price to pay” was  
one of general application to all employees, and did not explicitly examine  
its deleterious consequences on separate groups. However, as preceding  
para. 483 later notes, NAPE’s counsel does make the differential by raising  
the continuing effects upon retirees and employees in receipt of worker  
compensation benefits as a separate issue. This approach is attractive as it  
seems more closely in keeping with the admonition sounded in McKinney,  
discussed in preceding paras. 513 to 515, that these analyses of  
proportionate effects should be undertaken with “considerable caution” in  
careful advertence to the factual matrix obtaining. It is for that reason that  
this judgment, following counsel’s format, will now turn to address  
separately the effects upon the second group.  
*
effects on retirees:  
[525] While retirees to pensions or worker compensation benefits within the  
highlighted time frame will have experienced the same deleterious effects of  
loss of salary adjustments during the period of their working days because  
of the measure’s postponement of the implementation of pay equity as  
fellow employees who continued to work throughout it, the measure’s  
effects upon those retirees transcended salary loss. This is because the  
levels of pensions and such benefits are calibrated with reference to the  
levels of salaries in the last years of their employment. Hence the  
deprivations of the pay equity adjustments as promised within the April 1,  
1988, to March 31, 1996, eight year time frame would have had a  
deleterious effect on pensions and benefits of employees retiring in those  
years. Indeed, its impact on that account would be more discriminatory  
inasmuch as the effect on employees continuing in their work would be  
temporary whilst, as NAPE’s counsel correctly points out, it would wreak  
permanent deleterious effects on women who retired from the work force, or  
were forced on compensation, within that time frame. As she states, such  
persons would never realize the benefit of pay equity promises made  
Page: 196  
towards the end of their careers, and the discrimination against them would  
continue during the rest of their lifetimes in the case of pensioners, and for  
the duration of receipt of benefits in the cases of those forced on workers  
compensation.  
[526] There is no doubt, then, that the strongest challenge mounted by NAPE to  
the judge’s holding that the deleterious effect of the measure was not “too  
high a price to pay” lies in its impact on retirees from the work force. It  
needs to be reiterated, however, that that deleterious impact does not stem  
from the incremental approach to pay equity continued by the restraint  
measure. It rather flows from the measure’s postponement of  
implementation of the incremental process originally settled upon as the  
method of progressing to full pay equity.  
[527] That deferral effectuated through the restraint measure cannot summarily be  
dismissed as merely putting off pay equity’s realization on the same  
incremental basis as originally provided, as preceding para. 484 indicates  
the argument of Government’s counsel is wont to do. Neither may the  
deleterious effect of the postponement be rationalized by the fact that  
Legislatures have “leeway” and “should not be obliged to deal with all  
aspects of a problem at once”, as para. 507 of this judgment records  
LaForest J. to have affirmed in McKinney and, upon which preceding para.  
84 recounts the decision under appellate scrutiny at bar relies, albeit in the  
context of incrementalism rather than of postponement which is the proper  
focus of the measure’s deleterious impact, in reasoning that the impugned  
legislative measure’s restraint on pay equity payments met the  
proportionality criterion laid down in Oakes.  
[528] There is, therefore, no basis to minimize or deprecate the deleterious effect  
of the measure’s infringement of the affected employees s. 15(1)  
constitutionally protected equality rights. The postponement of  
implementation of the promised pay equity wrought serious consequences to  
the enjoyment of those rights to all employees affected by that measure.  
The harm was exacerbated for those falling within the group who retired, or  
were forced on workers compensation, within the eight year time frame  
when the measure’s effect was being experienced, however. This was  
particularly so in the cases of retirees who would never receive the full  
benefit of the deferred pay equity promises, and would suffer permanent  
discrimination compared with their former counterparts who remained  
employed.  
Page: 197  
[529] While fully appreciative of the more pernicious effect of the violation of the  
individual equality rights upon the second group of affected employees,  
despite the compounded negative impact of the restraint measure on those  
retirees, the impugned measure must still be reckoned justifiable by its  
intended purposes of containing and reducing the forecasted mushrooming  
deficits. While there is no room to discount the severity of the deleterious  
effects of that measure’s limitation of s. 15(1) equality rights, careful  
analysis of the circumstances in which it was enacted supports the judge’s  
holding that those individual rights were outweighed by the critical  
importance of the objective which the legislative postponement of the  
individual Charter rights was intended to serve.  
[530] In this regard, it is relevant to note the restraint legislation had impact on  
public sector remuneration beyond its postponement of pay equity. Thus, as  
pointed out in Newfoundland Prov. Ct. Judges, the restraint legislation  
also imposed a general freeze on wage scales throughout the public service.  
However, it can be anticipated that those caught in the wage scale freeze  
who retired in the period of the restraints, and in the time thereafter in which  
the freezes would have affected their pensions or benefits, would likewise  
have experienced adverse effects on their pension or compensation benefits.  
It is fully recognized that this comparison is not entirely apt since the  
women retiring from the bargaining units promised pay equity within the  
time frame when their pensions and benefits would have been also affected  
by the wage scale freeze would experience the additional impact of the pay  
equity postponement. Moreover, the relative effect is not comparable  
because those affected solely by the wage freeze would not have had to  
suffer the indignity of their contributions in the workplace being  
underesteemed. Nevertheless, the effect of the restraint legislation’s general  
salary scale freeze is worthy of mention as it tends to underscore the gravity  
of the measure’s objective.  
[531] Apart from the wage scale freeze’s relevance, however, in looking to the  
language of s. 1 of the Charter, in which judicial authority directs the  
appropriate standard of justification must be found, it is hard to discern how  
the restraint measure’s intrusion in the circumstances at bar could be  
deemed otherwise than reasonably justifiable in free and democratic society  
when taking into account its intrusion’s deleterious effects upon the retirees,  
as well as upon the first group of affected employees. The justifiability of  
those effects stems from the urgency and gravity of the fiscal situation  
Page: 198  
described in the overlooked “extended budgetary explanation” which  
portended future governmental incapacity to provide health, educational and  
social services essential to maintain the basic fabric of free and democratic  
society.  
[532] The critical importance of the legislative measure’s objective in addressing  
the problem posed by the forecasted deficits hovering over the Province in  
1991 has already been sufficiently underscored in preceding discussion of  
the impugned measure’s proportionate effects vis à vis its objective. There  
is no need to further belabour that point. It only remains to add that the  
heightened discriminatory effect on retirees is not sufficient to warrant  
revisiting the general assessment of the restraint legislation’s justification  
reached in the foregoing analyses of its objective’s importance, and of the  
first two components of the proportionality test.  
[533] In the result, notwithstanding its increased negative impact upon retirees, it  
is reasonable to conclude the restraint legislation’s objective outweighs its  
deleterious effect on all employees who were affected by it. Therefore,  
considering the “extended explanatory explanation”, and the clear omens it  
portended for the Province’s future capacity to provide essential communal  
needs, the Legislature must be deemed to have had rational and serious  
grounds to have infringed those employees’ s. 15(1) equality rights by  
postponement of the promised pay equity process. This being so, applying  
the deferential standard of justification of Charter infringements that this  
judgment has concluded authority signifies to be appropriate, agreement  
must be voiced with the judge’s conclusion that the Arbitration Board’s  
majority erred in concluding the benefit of attaining the restraint measure’s  
objective was “too high a price to pay”. While preferring to direct focus on  
pay equity’s postponement, rather than its incremental implementation, the  
judge’s ultimate conclusion is nonetheless unassailable where, as preceding  
para. 84 recounts, he held that the “severe fiscal problem” faced at the time  
of the restraint’s enactment led to reasonable conclusion that “the law did  
not have a disproportionately severe effect” upon the employees whose  
individual Charter rights were violated by the impugned measure.  
*
consonance with Doctrine:  
[534] As heralded in preceding para. 372, and was undertaken at the end of the  
foregoing canvassing of each stage of the Oakes s. 1 justification criteria,  
attention will now focus on the consonance with the Separation of Powers  
Page: 199  
Doctrine of the foregoing affirmation of the judge’s conclusion that the  
proportionate effects component had been fulfilled in the circumstances at  
bar. As was the case with the rational connection component, fulfillment of  
this third and final component of the proportionality test can be reached in  
consort with the Doctrine essentially because it entailed no inquiry into  
whether other means existed which visited a less deleterious effect upon the  
infringed equality rights whilst attaining the measure’s important purposes  
of containing and reducing the looming serious fiscal deficits. Being  
confined to the measure actually adopted, i.e. the postponing pay equity  
adjustments, the conclusion that its consequential Charter violation was not  
“too high a price to pay” can likewise be viewed as an exercise of judicial  
power akin to the court’s traditional statutory interpretative role of  
construing the effect of legislative measures. Thus, as was the case with the  
judge’s rational connection holding, his finding that the deleterious effect of  
the measure’s violation was not disproportionate to its objective’s  
importance must be accepted as also made within acceptable bounds in  
consonance both with s. 1 and the Doctrine.  
*
affirmation of effects finding:  
[535] For the foregoing reasons, the judge’s overturning of the determination by  
the Arbitration Board’s majority that the deleterious effect of the measure’s  
violation of the s. 15(1) equality rights was “too high a price to pay” to  
attain its objective should be upheld. The three challenges raised by counsel  
for NAPE to the judge’s finding that the restraint measure had no  
disproportionately severe effect rendering it unjustifiable by the purposes it  
was intended to serve emerge from the preceding discussions as  
unsustainable in full light of the circumstances at bar.  
[536] Firstly, while the import of the measure’s infringement is incontrovertible,  
the importance of addressing the fiscal deficits that the evidence showed to  
be threatening the Province’s economic security and well-being was of  
sufficient magnitude to outweigh and override the violation. Secondly,  
counsel’s incrementalism argument, unsupported by the authorities  
submitted in response to it when considered in the context of the  
circumstances obtaining, is irrelevant because it was the postponement of  
the scheduled implementation of the pay equity process, not its incremental  
means of achievement, which perpetrated the Charter rights’ violation.  
Thirdly, the deleterious effects of the violative postponement upon retirees,  
Page: 200  
as a result of its permanent effects upon their pensions or compensation  
benefits, is still justifiable when weighed against the urgency and gravity  
deducible from the ministerial “extended budgetary explanation” that had  
been overlooked by the Arbitration Board.  
[537] It should be noted here it is on the basis of the deferential flexible standard  
commanded by authority for the conduct of justification analyses under s. 1  
of the Charter, that it has been concluded the severity of the impugned  
legislative measure’s intrusion upon the s. 15(1) equality rights through its  
postponement of pay equity is justifiable by the purposes it was intended to  
serve. Moreover, this conclusion is reached fully mindful of the hybrid  
deferential standard for conducting and reviewing s. 1 analyses, which has  
already been fully discussed, and is summarized in preceding paras. 272 to  
275. In particular, the conclusion is taken fully alert to the demarcation  
made by the majority in RJR-MacDonald suggesting a lesser degree of  
deference to policy oriented evidence than that of a purely factual nature.  
[538] In this regard, it is observed that the evidence which precipitated the  
restraint legislation’s enactment consisted, as the ministerial “extended  
budgetary explanation” of it witnesses, of pure economic facts. It is neither  
classifiable as social science, nor as other policy oriented evidence. This  
being so, this court is not in any position to dispute the financial situation  
portrayed by the Minister of Finance to the Legislature. Neither has it any  
mandate to do so on even the most restrictive view of the s. 1 justification  
standard of deference if any semblance of harmony with the Separation of  
Powers Doctrine is to be maintained. In any event, even if aspects of policy  
can be said to have prompted the rights intrusion, as already noted, whatever  
the consequential restricted deferential standard, the judge’s finding of  
justification would be sustainable in light of the grave threat to the  
economic security and well being of the Province.  
[539] The upshot of this upholding of the judge’s finding of fulfillment of the  
proportionality component of the proportionality test results in affirmation  
of his conclusion that the infringement of the s. 15(1) Charter equality  
rights is saved by justification under s. 1, and resolution of the  
constitutional issue at bar.  
Dispositions to date:  
Page: 201  
[540] At this juncture, before proceeding to discussion of the remaining issues  
listed in preceding para. 108, it is timely to take stock of those that have  
been resolved.  
[541] The first was the jurisdictional issue discussed in preceding paras. 109 to  
175. That issue was resolved in siding with NAPE counsel’s submission  
that the judge erred in holding the Arbitration Board lacked jurisdiction to  
hear the grievances. Had analysis resulted in agreement with the latter’s  
view that the pay equity dispute at bar did not arise out of the Collective  
Agreement, this judgment would have sided with the holding that the Board  
was not empowered to hear these complaints, and the appeal could have  
ended on that finding. Such not being the result, attention then turned to  
issues (ii) and (iii) listed in preceding para. 108 dealing with the  
constitutionality of the legislated restraint measure.  
[542] These constitutional issues are discussed in paras. 176 through to 275.  
Attention focused at the beginning of that discussion on the standards of  
judicial review of the Arbitration Board’s decisions construing both the  
restraint legislation’s language and its constitutional invalidity. Having first  
set out the contextual setting of that discussion in preceding paras. 176 to  
180, the judgment canvassed in paras. 181 to 213 the test to be applied in  
review of the Board’s statutory interpretation of the wording in s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation, concluding that its standard was patent  
unreasonableness.  
[543] Discussion then turned to the standard of review of the Arbitration Board’s  
unanimous ruling that s. 9 perpetrated a violation of affected employees’ s.  
15(1) Charter equality rights. This phase of the judgment was undertaken  
in paras. 214 to 252 where, after detailing reasons for reservations over the  
test not being the same deferential one applicable in traditional statutory  
interpretations, it was acknowledged that the law requires such arbitral  
rulings be reviewable on the standard of correctness, and that that norm  
would be applied in the circumstances at bar.  
[544] Finally, in paras. 253 to 275, focus was centered on the judicial standard of  
s. 1 Charter justification analyses. In that segment of the discussion, it was  
explained why the standard in that inquiry laid down in RJR-MacDonald is  
more complex and does not crystalize into an absolute norm. Analysis of  
authoritative judicial opinion on the topic led to conclusion that the  
appropriate deferential and flexible standard for the justification analysis at  
bar, mirroring the wording of s. 1, would be that which would give sway to  
Page: 202  
the limitation in issue if determined to be a reasonable limit demonstrably  
justifiable in a free and democratic society.  
[545] Applying these standards, following the format for consideration of the  
issues in this appeal, attention then centered on Government counsel’s  
submission that the judge’s ruling affirming the unanimous arbitral decision  
that the restraint measure infringed s. 15(1) of the Charter was correct.  
This dispensed with the second of the issues listed in preceding para. 108.  
[546] After siding with counsel’s submission that the judge’s infringement ruling  
should be upheld, consideration was then directed to whether the violation  
was nonetheless saved under s. 1 of the Charter. This is the third of the  
listed issues, and the second arm of the constitutional question. This inquiry  
resulted in agreement being accorded to Government counsel’s submission  
that the judge’s ruling that the violation was redeemed under s. 1 of the  
Charter should be upheld. This ruling overturned the Board’s contrary  
view, and thereby confirmed the restraint measure’s legal effectiveness and  
enforceability in accordance with the import of its terms.  
[547] In resolving the constitutional issue thusly, this judgment was guided by the  
criteria handed down in Oakes, and other subsequent authorities expanding  
upon them, for the conduct of s. 1 Charter analyses. Its reasoning in  
affirmation of the judge’s constitutional dispositions also proceeded on the  
footing that the Charter’s purpose and intent is to place effective measures  
in the hands of individuals of enforcing their entrenched fundamental rights  
and freedoms to the extent that no rational objection to the enjoyment of  
them could be maintained in free and democratic society. As was explained,  
conducting the analyses on that basis assures alertness to the reality that in  
achieving its purpose and intent the Charter wrought a dramatic change in  
parliamentary supremacy as traditionally operative in the parliamentary  
systems of government to which it applied. That change is manifested in  
the power it confers upon the judiciary to declare executive and legislative  
actions and laws unenforceable for want of justification of their interference  
with enjoyment of individual entrenched Charter rights.  
[548] By the same token, it is equally noteworthy that the foregoing constitutional  
analysis was also conducted from the standpoint that the Charter effected  
no such similar fundamentally radical change in the policy making powers  
of the three branches of government under the Separation of Powers  
Doctrine. Instead, it proceeded on the basis that the guardianship of  
individual fundamental rights and freedoms conferred on the judiciary by  
Page: 203  
the Charter extended the courts’ interpretative role to ascertaining the  
impact of governmental measures on guaranteed rights; but bestowed no  
increased policy-making power for that purpose beyond that normally  
exercisable by courts in discharging their traditional interpretative role.  
This premise follows from authoritative confirmation that the Separation of  
Powers Doctrine is just as much a distinguishing feature of the Canadian  
Constitution as the Charter has become. It is for this reason that the  
various stages of analysis of the judge’s treatment of the restraint measure’s  
compatibility with the Charter were also addressed for its consonance with  
the Doctrine. The upshot of this approach is affirmation that the judge’s  
conclusion holding the impugned legislation to be constitutionally  
enforceable was made within acceptable bounds, in consonance with both s.  
1 of the Charter and the Doctrine as it has traditionally operated.  
[549] Having resolved the judge’s conclusion that s. 9 of the Public Sector  
Restraint Act met constitutional muster because the s. 15(1) violation it  
perpetrated was nonetheless justifiable under s. 1 of the Charter should be  
upheld, this appeal now moves to consider whether the judge’s  
interpretation of the meaning and thrust of that constitutionally enforceable  
legislation is sustainable.  
The statutory interpretation issue:  
÷
separate arms of issue:  
[550] As reference to preceding para. 108 will show, the statutory interpretation  
issue is subdivided into two parts, therein listed as issues (iv) and (v). Both  
were raised by NAPE in its challenge of the judge’s agreement with the  
Arbitration Board’s construction of s. 9 of the restraint legislation. The first  
arm of the challenge asks whether that provision extinguished  
Government’s obligation to make pay equity wage adjustments under the  
Pay Equity Agreement between April 1, 1988, and March 31, 1991, in light  
of the first three wage adjustment payment dates scheduled under the  
Agreement having passed before Government was in a position to respond  
to its undertakings to make those adjustments. As noted at the outset of this  
judgment in preceding para. 8, this situation arose because the financial  
consultants’ report providing the requisite calculations of the quantum of  
the wage and adjustments necessary to erase the systemic gender  
discrimination within the affected groups was not finalized until March 20,  
Page: 204  
1991, and not received by the steering committee until July of 1991. In  
these circumstances, the earliest date when the adjustments could have  
commenced was April 1, 1991, which was the fourth wage adjustment date  
in the original timetable for the achievement of pay equity under the Pay  
Equity Agreement; but the “1st pay equity adjustment date” after the final  
determination of the amount of the discrepancy due to gender on March 20,  
1991.  
[551] The second arm of the statutory interpretation issue questions the judge’s  
agreement with the conclusion that Government was not required to pay the  
full wage rate entitlement on April 1, 1992, which would have been  
receivable by affected employees under the Agreement but for the  
legislated restraints. As already noted in preceding paras. 42 and 99, this  
second arm of the statutory interpretation issue asserts NAPE’s primary  
alternate challenge to the judge’s affirmation of the Board majority’s  
interpretation that s-s. 9(3) erased Government’s obligation to provide pay  
equity prior to April 1, 1991. It flows from the argument of NAPE’s  
counsel that, even if the obligation to pay wage adjustments were  
extinguished between June 24, 1988, and April 1, 1991, because the amount  
of the adjustments were not ascertained until March 20, 1991, the scheduled  
obligations to make the fourth year adjustment and to pay the balance of the  
promised pay equity with effect from June 24, 1988, in the fifth year  
nonetheless continued unabated. This alternate position, therefore,  
effectively argues, if s. 9 is to be construed as extinguishing rights to  
receive pay equity during the restraint period, it only effectuated a  
suspensive deferral of the entitlements. In the result, NAPE is arguing in  
this submission that those deferred payments became payable April 1, 1992,  
as part of the balance needed to achieve full pay equity on the fifth  
anniversary of the first effective payment date in accordance with the terms  
of the Pay Equity Agreement.  
[552] The merits of these arms of the statutory interpretation challenge arising out  
of the Arbitration Board’s construction of the restraint legislation’s  
language will now be addressed separately. As was already indicated in  
preceding para. 270, and elsewhere in the discussion of the standards of  
judicial review applicable to this appeal’s issues, these challenges to the  
judge’s affirmation of the statutory interpretation of the Board’s majority,  
encapsulated in issues (iv) and (v) listed in preceding para. 108, will be  
conducted on the patently unreasonable standard.  
Page: 205  
÷
the extinguishment issue:  
crux of issue:  
>
[553] At this point it would be useful to review the legislative provision to be  
interpreted, which is reproduced in preceding para. 11, together with the  
respective summaries of the treatments of the extinguishment issue in the  
Board chairperson’s majority decision summarized in preceding paras. 20 to  
25; in the union nominee’s in preceding paras. 38 to 41; and, in the judge’s  
affirmation of the majority disposition in preceding paras. 91 to 98.  
[554] From this review, it will be seen that the kernel of this extinguishment issue  
boils down to whether s-s. 9(3)’s sanctioning of implementations of pay  
equity agreements on “on the date on which the pay equity adjustment was  
agreed upon” meant adjustments were permitted to commence,  
notwithstanding the enacted restraints, on “the date when the commitment to  
institute pay equity was reached”, as NAPE’s counsel argued, or on the date  
“upon which the amount of the pay equity adjustment is determined”, as  
preceding para. 97 records was the judge’s construction in disagreement  
with NAPE’s position. If the first construction is the proper one, given it  
was common ground that s-s. 9(1) and s-s. 9(2) eliminated governmental  
obligation to pay equity prior to June 24, 1988, being the date of its  
committal to the obligation on its entry into the Pay Equity Agreement,  
Government’s obligation between June 24, 1988, and March 31,1991,  
would subsist. If the second one is interpreted to be the meaning, all  
obligation prior to March 31, 1991, would be extinguished. The liability at  
stake in these proceedings, therefore, is the entitlement to pay equity for the  
period spanning June 24, 1988, and March 31, 1991.  
[555] It is important in this inquiry into the extinguishment question to bear in  
mind that s. 9 of the Public Sector Restraint Act did not prohibit entry  
into, or implementation of, pay equity agreements during the period of the  
restraints. This is clear from s-s. 9(4). However, the legislative measure did  
place restrictions upon the right to exact payments under any such  
agreement. Determination whether it precluded payments between June 24,  
1988, and March 31, 1991 hinges on whether the critical phrase “the date on  
which the pay equity adjustment was agreed upon” in s-s. 9(3) eliminated  
Government’s obligation to make payments within that period on the  
ground that the amount of the pay equity adjustments remained to be  
Page: 206  
determined on the payment dates scheduled under the Agreement until  
shortly before expiry of the 1990-91 fiscal year, the report of the financial  
consultants not having been finalized under March 20, 1991.  
[556] It is equally important to keep to the fore that the Pay Equity Agreement  
appended to the Collective Agreements affected by the outcome of this  
appeal was in existence at the time of passage of s. 9 of the restraint  
legislation. This being so, it is reasonable to assume the Legislature, when  
enacting the restraint measure, would have been fully alert to the  
Agreement’s existence, and to the fact that the amount of the pay equity  
adjustments had not been determined until finalization of the report of the  
financial consultants on March 20, 1991, providing calculation of the  
quantum of the pay equity wage adjustments. As will be presently  
observed, it is that knowledge which gives context to the chairperson’s  
comment, reproduced in the extract from his decision quoted in preceding  
para. 21, that s-s. 9(3) designed the method by which “pay equity  
adjustments were subject to restraint”. Likewise, that knowledge, in its  
contextual setting of s-s. 9(3), as has already been described in preceding  
paras. 93 to 98, supplies perspective to the judge’s holding that the restraint  
legislation “clearly extinguished Government’s obligation to make pay  
equity wage adjustments for the period prior to the date when the  
adjustments were agreed upon”, which would have included the entire  
period of the restraints prior to their expiry on March 31, 1991. Moreover,  
as will shortly become apparent, it is also this knowledge which will play an  
important role in the ensuing analysis of the arguments addressed to the  
challenge of that holding of the judge.  
>
arguments of counsel:  
[557] Counsel for NAPE submits the Board’s majority and the judge erred in  
finding s. 9 of the restraint legislation extinguished Government’s  
obligation to provide pay equity adjustments for the period between June  
24, 1988, and March 31, 1991. Echoing the reasoning of the union’s  
nominee to the Board in that regard, summarized in preceding paras. 38 to  
42, and consistently with her position throughout these proceedings, counsel  
for NAPE insists that the central question on which the resolution of this  
extinguishment issue hinges is answered by giving the critical phrase “the  
date on which the pay equity adjustment is agreed upon” in s-s. 9(3) its clear  
unambiguous meaning, which she maintains is the date “when the  
Page: 207  
commitment to institute pay equity was reached”, i.e. June 24, 1988, “when  
the Pay Equity Agreement was signed”, and “not the date when the specific  
amount was determined”. As already noted, the latter date was March 20,  
1991, when the financial consultant’s report was finalized.  
[558] In arguing that s-s. 9(3's) meaning is clear, counsel for NAPE nonetheless  
posits, if any ambiguity exists, it is “a cardinal principle of statutory  
interpretation that collective agreements and rights contained thereunder  
should not be abrogated by an interpretation of legislation unless such  
interpretation is clearly mandated by the wording of the statute”.  
Proceeding from thence, enlisting authorities to support her point, she also  
submits that “any ambiguity in section 9 of the Act must be resolved in  
favour of ... the interpretation which accords with the Charter and the  
values to which it gives expression”. From both standpoints NAPE’s  
counsel goes on to contend it to be “... inexorable conclusion that the  
legislation must be interpreted as not affecting the payment of the amounts  
required to achieve pay equity”. It is from these positions, then, that NAPE  
attacks the judge’s affirmation of the finding of the Board’s majority that  
Government’s obligation was extinguished.  
[559] Government’s counsel responds by arguing the “language contained in  
section 9 is not ambiguous and can be given only one clear meaning”.  
Thus, quoting from the phrase in s-s. 9(3) stipulating “... the 1st pay equity  
wage adjustment date shall be the date on which the pay equity adjustment  
is agreed upon”, counsel submits that that “first ... adjustment date” must be  
construed as “the date when the specific amount was determined and not the  
date when the commitment to institute pay equity was reached”. He  
maintains this intent emerges clearly from the ordinary and natural meaning  
of the wording of the phrase, from its contextual setting within s. 9 and the  
Act as a whole, as well as from the provision’s purpose.  
[560] It is from this perspective, then, that Government maintains it to be clear  
that “the date on which pay equity wage adjustment payments were to  
commence was the date on which the amount of wage increases had been  
agreed upon”. It agrees that this date was March 20, 1991, when the  
amounts of the wage adjustments had been finally calculated by the  
financial consultants. Echoing the chairperson’s comment quoted in  
preceding para. 22, counsel for Government submits, while this would have  
resulted in a three year payout falling due on April 1, 1991, but for the  
Page: 208  
interpretation of s. 9 of the restraint legislation, s-s. 9(3)’s clear thrust was  
to eliminate the obligation to make that retroactive payout.  
>
approach to s. 9's interpretation:  
[561] As their arguments show, both counsel open with their perspectives of the  
clarity of s-s. 9(3)'s critical phrase which links the first pay equity  
adjustment date of pay equity agreements to the date on which such wage  
adjustments are agreed upon. Counsel for NAPE takes the position the  
phrase clearly and unambiguously demarks the date of agreement as the day  
when the pay equity commitment was made on the signing of the Agreement  
on June 24, 1988. Counsel for Government, equally adamantly, insists it  
clearly and unambiguously means the date when the financial consultants’  
report was finalized on March 20, 1991, thereby eliminating the obligation  
for retroactive payments, and opening the way for the commencement of the  
pay equity wage adjustment payments.  
[562] The first thing that needs be said with respect to these opening salvos of  
both counsel is that rarely can questions of statutory interpretation be  
resolved solely by touting lack of ambiguities. This is simply because  
definitions are not mathematical formulas leading to precise solution of  
import. The meaning of language is not construable as if its definition were  
an algebraic equation. There is no doubt that resort to dictionary definition  
is an important first step. However, as in any appreciation of meaning,  
context is also a very relevant consideration. In statutory interpretation the  
purpose of the legislation is also a particularly important factor to be  
considered. Appreciation of contextual and purposive factors will  
necessarily entail advertence to the circumstances in which the words are  
used. The importance of such circumstances was noted by the judge in his  
reference to the frequently quoted observation in Escoigne Properties Ltd.  
v. Inland Revenue Commissioners, [1958] 1 All E.R. 406 [H.L.] where  
Lord Denning stated at p. 414:  
C
A statute is not passed in a vacuum, but in a framework of  
circumstances, so as to give a remedy for a known state of affairs. To  
arrive at its true meaning, you should know the circumstances with  
reference to which the words were used; and what was the object  
appearing from those circumstances which Parliament had in view.  
[563] In the result, Government counsel’s assertion that the legislative intent of s.  
9 is to be construed from a composite of ordinary and natural meaning,  
Page: 209  
contextual setting and purpose discernible within the “framework of  
circumstances” of the statutory measure’s enactment is an accurate  
description of the recognized statutory interpretative process. His assertion  
is supported by R. v. Lewis, [1996] 1 S.C.R 921, which counsel enlists to  
support that submission. In Lewis, Iacobucci J., writing on behalf of a  
unanimous bench, addressed the meaning of “on” in the phrase “on the  
reserve”. In so doing, endorsing the views expressed in the texts of  
Professors P.-A. Coté and Ruth Sullivan, Iacobucci J. indicated in para. 66  
of Lewis that the proper approach was to address the phrase’s meaning by  
analyzing “the wording, context and purpose of the statutory provision”.  
[564] It should be noted before proceeding to this three-pronged analysis that no  
exception is taken with the propositions of counsel for NAPE that in face of  
ambiguities courts should lean against statutory constructions that abrogate  
collective agreements, and towards interpretations favouring realization of  
Charter rights. These propositions neither obviate the need for analysis,  
nor provide any instant resolution to the import of statutory measures,  
however. They only apply where analysis of meaning leads to an impasse  
of credible ambiguity. In other words, the statutory interpretative process  
must first be conducted, and have resulted in conclusion that the language  
employed is capable of being understood in more than one sense. This was  
made clear in one of the authorities enlisted by counsel for NAPE to this  
aspect of her submissions. Thus, in R. v. Zundel, [1992] 2 S.C.R. 731,  
McLachlin J. summarized the case law on the application of the principle at  
p. 771 as follows:  
C
... where a legislative provision, on a reasonable interpretation of its  
history and on the plain meaning of its text, is subject to two equally  
persuasive interpretations, the Court should adopt that interpretation  
which accords with the Charter and the values to which it gives  
expression ....  
[565] It will be noted that Zundel’s call to “history” and “plain reading” reflects  
the approach to statutory interpretation sanctioned in Lewis, and other  
authority, of focusing on plain meaning, context and purpose, whilst being  
fully alert to the “framework of circumstances” under which the legislative  
language under scrutiny was passed. The affirmability of the judge’s  
upholding of the interpretation placed on s. 9 of the Public Sector  
Restraint Act by the Arbitration Board’s majority will now be subjected to  
that approach.  
Page: 210  
>
extinguishment finding’s affirmation:  
[566] The judge’s treatment, summarized in preceding paras. 91 to 98, witnesses  
adherence to that approach in his upholding of the Arbitration Board’s  
majority ruling that s-s. 9(3) of the restraint legislation extinguished  
Government’s obligation to provide pay equity adjustments up to the expiry  
of the statutory restraints on March 31, 1991.  
*
plain meaning factor:  
[567] As preceding paras. 96 and 97 indicate, the judge commenced his inquiry  
into the extinguishment arm of the statutory interpretation issue by looking,  
through resort to dictionary definition, to the plain meaning of the words  
“wage adjustment” in s-s. 9(3) in exposing the weakness of the failure of  
NAPE to lend “consequence” in its construction of the import of these  
words within that provision. Speaking strictly from the plain meaning of  
those key words, the judge’s reasoning in that regard has coherence and  
rationality. It affords compellingly persuasive support to his conclusion that  
the critical phrase in s-s. 9(3), in identifying the date when the “1st pay  
equity wage adjustment” could be payable as “the date upon which the pay  
equity wage adjustment is agreed upon”, had thereby stipulated the earliest  
permissible wage adjustment payment date during the restraint period, in the  
judge’s words, had to be held to the date “upon which the amount of the pay  
equity adjustment is determined”.  
*
contextual factor:  
[568] The judge did not rest his conclusion on his assessment of plain meaning of  
the critical wording of s-s. 9(3), however. As mentioned in the resumé of  
the extinguishment aspect of his decision, he also placed weight on the  
context of s-s. 9(3)’s enactment. Actually, a perusal of his reasoning  
suggests he laid particular emphasis on the contextual factor. In doing so,  
his analysis made mention that the Hansard confirmed “the details of the  
Pay Equity Agreement were known to members of the Legislature”. This  
led him to read “the language in Section 9 of the Act ... in the context of the  
Pay Equity Agreement”, which resulted, in turn, in him concluding from the  
provision’s contextual setting “that the phrase ‘pay equity wage adjustment’  
in the Pay Equity Agreement refers to the amount of wage increase required  
to achieve pay equity”.  
Page: 211  
[569] This emphasis upon knowledge of the “details” of the governmental  
commitment to pay equity in the judge’s assessment of contextual impact  
upon the import of s. 9's language is significant to appreciation of the Board  
chairperson’s comment, quoted in preceding para. 21, that s-s. 9(3) designed  
the method by which “pay equity adjustments were subject to restraint”.  
Hence, knowledge of those “details” would have included awareness at the  
date of the provision’s passage into law on April 18, 1991 that the amount  
of the promised pay equity adjustment had not been determined until the  
previous March 20th when the consultants’ report was finalized. Although  
the financial consultant’s report may have been finalized in the latter days of  
March of that year, the evidence confirms it was not in Government’s  
possession by the time of the restraint legislation’s enactment.  
[570] The upshot of this state of legislative knowledge at the time of enactment  
gives context to the judge’s observation that s-s. 9(3) provides a method of  
subjecting the pay equity adjustments to restraint. Thus, in imputing  
legislative knowledge that the quantum of adjustments, payable under the  
Pay Equity Agreement to employees in the six bargaining units within the  
public health sector, had not been determined until March 20, 1991, it is  
quite logical to infer that the legislators understood s-s. 9(3)’s holding of the  
“1st pay equity adjustment date” of any “pay equity agreement ...  
implemented” during the period of restraints to “the date on which the pay  
equity wage adjustment is agreed upon” meant that the governmental  
obligation to make the retroactive wage adjustment payments, which would  
otherwise have fallen due, was extinguished. This is simply because “the  
date on which the pay equity wage adjustment is agreed upon” had not  
arrived before March 20, 1991. Therein lies the contextual explanation of  
the chairperson’s observation recorded in preceding para. 21 that s-s. 9(3) of  
the restraint legislation designed the method by which “pay equity  
adjustments were subject to restraint”.  
[571] By the same token, this contextual setting of legislative knowledge lends a  
clear perspective of reasonableness to the judge’s upholding of the Board’s  
extinguishment ruling on its judicial review. No exception can be taken that  
that context lends significant weight to the judge’s holding that the restraint  
legislation “and particularly Section 9 thereof, clearly extinguished  
Government’s obligation ...”. Certainly, the knowledge which must be  
imputed to the Legislature militates against any holding on judicial review  
of patent unreasonableness of the Board’s conclusion that “(t)he language of  
Page: 212  
s. 9 ... had the effect of extinguishing the obligations on government ... to  
provide pay equity adjustments for the period April 1, 1988 to March 31,  
1991". Likewise, this same bed of knowledge supports this Court affirming  
the judge’s treatment of the contextual factor as reasonable.  
*
purposive factor:  
[572] The judge’s treatment of s-s. 9(3)’s purpose centered on consideration of the  
objective “of section 9 in its entirety and the Act as a whole”. Thus, after  
observing that the legislation limited “the cost to Government of salaries  
and other benefits paid to public sector employees”, the judge’s decision  
went on to state:  
C
[126] ... Section 9 dealt with the treatment to be accorded pay equity  
agreements as defined in subsection(5). Subsections (1) and (2)  
forbade the retroactive implementation of pay equity agreements  
thereby limiting Government’s liability. Subsection (3) had a primary  
and a secondary purpose. The primary purpose was to permit the  
negotiation or implementation of pay equity agreements despite the  
other provisions of the Act. The secondary purpose was to impose a  
limitation on the establishment of the “1st pay equity wage adjustment  
date”. In the context of the Act as a whole the likely intent of the  
limitation would be to reduce Government’s financial exposure in the  
implementation of pay equity agreements.  
[573] No sustainable quarrel can be taken with this statement of purpose of s-s.  
9(3), nor with its relevancy to the present inquiry into whether s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation admits to being interpreted as extinguishing  
governmental obligation to make pay equity adjustments which, but for the  
legislative intervention, would have fallen due on the consultants’  
finalization of quantification of the amounts payable. However, in her  
submissions, NAPE’s counsel maintains s. 9 also had another purpose  
which must be considered, namely: the abrogation of commitments in  
collective agreements with which, in the absence of clear language that she  
maintains is lacking in s. 9, legislation is presumed not to intend to interfere.  
It will be noted that these positions of NAPE have already been addressed in  
preceding para. 564 where it was concluded that credible ambiguity must be  
construable in the legislation before any such presumptions became  
operative. The judge dealt with counsel’s argument in the same vein.  
Hence, while acknowledging the “indisputable” validity of both principles,  
Page: 213  
he stated they “are only applicable where the language of the legislation is  
ambiguous”. In the case of s. 9, he concluded there was no ambiguity  
regarding extinguishment of Government’s obligation. As just noted, that  
conclusion has already received affirmation.  
[574] Returning to the judge’s statement of s-s. 9(3)’s purpose, the accuracy of its  
description as a measure intended “to reduce Government’s financial  
exposure in the implementation of pay equity agreements” cannot be  
gainsaid. This, in turn, can be seen to further the restraint legislation’s  
overall purpose of containing and reducing the forecasted escalating deficits  
that threatened the Province’s economic security and well-being. As  
Government counsel points out, the purpose of the limitation on the  
implementation of the pay equity agreements was “to avoid payment  
amounts that had not been paid as of the commencement of the restraint  
period”. Accordingly, as in the case of the contextual factor, the purpose of  
the restraint legislation buttresses the conclusion that no holding of patent  
unreasonableness could be maintained on judicial review with respect to the  
conclusion of the Board’s majority that s. 9's language extinguished  
Government’s obligations for pay equity adjustments prior to March 31,  
1991.  
*
upshot of analysis:  
[575] The judge conducted his review of the Arbitration Board’s extinguishment  
finding on the appropriate standard applying judicially endorsed legal  
principles. Construed in the light of its plain meaning, context and purpose,  
the conclusion of the Board’s majority that s. 9 of the restraint legislation  
extinguished Government’s obligations to make provision for pay equity  
during the restraint period April 1, 1988 and March 31, 1991 cannot be said  
to be a patently unreasonable interpretation. Accordingly, the judge’s  
upholding of that conclusion on judicial review is affirmed. Attention will  
now turn to the second arm of NAPE’s statutory interpretation challenge,  
being issue (v) listed in preceding para. 108.  
÷
the alternate position:  
essence of position:  
>
[576] As preceding para. 551 explains, NAPE’s alternate position is: even if s-s.  
9(3) were construed as extinguishing Government’s obligations to make pay  
Page: 214  
equity wage adjustments prior to finalization of quantification of the  
amounts payable in accordance with the Pay Equity Agreement’s terms, that  
provision still required these obligations to be fulfilled after the consultants’  
had agreed in their report on the amount of the pay equity wage adjustment.  
[577] At first blush, it might appear somewhat paradoxical to argue obligations  
accepted as extinguished by legislation can be construed nonetheless to be  
payable under the same statutory measure. This is not exactly what is being  
argued by counsel for NAPE, however. What really is being posited here is  
that the wage adjustment dates, scheduled prior to the consultants’  
determination of the amount of those adjustments on March 20, 1991, under  
the Pay Equity Agreement, were extinguished; but not the obligations to  
which those dates related. In effect, therefore, NAPE’s alternate measure  
interprets s-s. 9(3) as suspending wage adjustment obligations until the first  
wage adjustment date following finalization of the amounts payable by the  
financial consultants as contemplated by the Agreement. This was April 1,  
1991, which was the fourth pay equity wage adjustment date scheduled in  
the Pay Equity Agreement, but would have been “the lst pay equity wage  
adjustment date” under s-s. 9(3) of the restraint legislation inasmuch as “the  
pay equity wage adjustment” had not been “agreed upon” in this case until  
finalization of the financial consultants’ report on March 20, 1991.  
[578] The essential crux of the alternative challenge to the judge’s statutory  
interpretation, therefore, comes down to whether, given that the quantum of  
the pay equity wage adjustments necessary to implement the pay equity  
commitment was not determined until March 20, 1991, by the consultants,  
April 1, 1991, it is to be treated as the fourth wage adjustment date payable  
under the Pay Equity Agreement; or, “the 1st pay equity wage adjustment  
date” referenced to in s-s. 9(3) of the restraint legislation. If it be the  
former, then the remainder necessary to achieve the full promised pay equity  
would have fallen due on April 1, 1992, being the fifth anniversary of the  
first effective payment date under the Agreement. Under such a scenario, s-  
s. 9(3) is being construed as extinguishing the scheduled payment dates  
prior to the consultants’ determination of the amount of the adjustments on  
March 20, 1991; but not the obligations. In the result, the affected  
employees would receive the wage adjustments otherwise payable in the  
first three years under the Pay Equity Agreement, together with any  
remainder necessary to fulfil the original commitment to fully implement  
pay equity on the scheduled date of April, 1992. If April 1st, 1991, is to be  
Page: 215  
treated as the “1st pay equity wage adjustment date”, then the judge’s view  
that the schedule for commencement of the incremental payments had been  
shifted by s-s. 9(3) will prevail, and his affirmation of the Board’s rejection  
of NAPE’s alternate position on the statutory interpretation issue must be  
sustained.  
>
positions of counsel:  
[579] In submitting that the Arbitration Board’s majority and the judge erred in  
failing to find the wage adjustment that fell due on April 1, 1991, was to be  
treated under s-s. 9(3) of the legislation as the adjustment payable in the  
fourth year of the Pay Equity Agreement, counsel for NAPE was rejecting  
the thesis that the restraint legislation should be construed to have wrought  
a shift in the scheduled commencement of the incremental payments  
prescribed under the Agreement from April 1, 1988 to April 1, 1991.  
Instead, as has already been explained, counsel interprets s.9 as suspending  
the Agreement’s operation within that three year period, and effectively  
deferring the obligations within the suspension to the scheduled final  
payment date on April 1, 1992.  
[580] In advancing her position, counsel’s argument closely tracks the dissenting  
view of the union nominee to the Arbitration Board on this alternate  
statutory interpretation issue which is summarized in preceding paras. 42  
and 43. Thus, she adopts the dissent’s reasoning leading to the conclusion  
that “the balance of the pay equity adjustment was payable in accordance  
with the Pay Equity Agreement” under the legislation in the 1992-93 fiscal  
year. As already noted, this would result in that balance being payable April  
1, 1992, being the fifth and last scheduled payment date under the  
Agreement, and would include the three years of payment obligations  
NAPE construed to have been suspensively deferred.  
[581] Counsel also co-opts to her argument the union nominee’s position on  
Article 4.01 of the collective agreement, likewise underscoring the  
significance of finalization of the financial consultant’s report determining  
the amount of the discrepancy in wages attributable to gender, whilst  
arguing the continuation of differential wage rates constituted  
discrimination contrary to that Article. Recognizing, again following the  
dissent, that the statutory freezes on increases to pay scales did not end until  
March 31, 1993, she earmarked April 1, 1993, when there were no statutory  
restrictions on wage adjustments to redress the discrimination at which the  
Page: 216  
Agreement was aimed, as the date when full pay equity should have been  
achieved under the collective agreement.  
[582] This submission based on Article 4.01 is really a further alternative position  
put forth by NAPE, and as such will be separately addressed. At this  
juncture, it should be noted, however, that this further alternate would result  
in receipt of the full pay equity one year later than under the argument based  
exclusively on the legislation, and one year later than originally promised.  
From a practical point of view, the one year lapse was neither here nor there  
as far as the outcome sought through these proceedings is concerned since  
by the time the Arbitration hearings were held in 1995 the full amount of the  
pay equity would have been payable under either argument.  
[583] In his rejoinder, counsel for Government insists there was no basis to  
conclude that the legislation intended the payment that fell due on April 1,  
1991, should be treated as the adjustment payable in the fourth years of the  
Pay Equity Agreement as a result of the “pay equity wage adjustment”  
having been “agreed upon”, on March 20, 1991, with finalization of the  
consultants’ report. Instead, he argues, that based on “appropriate principles  
of interpretation”, the wage adjustments were payable “in accordance with  
the first rather than the fourth year of the Agreement”. Such conclusion, he  
maintains, follows “from a consideration of the effect of s. 9(3) of the Act,  
and the relationship between Article 4.01 of the Collective Agreement and  
Schedule H”. The referenced schedule was attached to the Pay Equity  
Agreement and had set out the incremental timetable in which pay equity  
had been intended to be fully achieved commencing with wage adjustments  
on April 1, 1988, and continuing on the 1st days of April thereafter to and  
including 1992 when the final settlement was slated to be paid.  
[584] In the result, from Government’s perspective, the judge was correct in  
viewing s-s. 9(3) as effecting a shift in the timetable for commencement of  
the incremental payments from April 1, 1988 to 1991. Accordingly, the  
previous three pay equity wage adjustment commitments were erased with  
the extinguishment of the obligations to pay them. The upshot of this would  
result in no significant three year payout including deferred payments  
having fallen due on April 1, 1992. Instead it would only have been the  
adjustment due on the “1st pay equity wage adjustment date”, in the words of  
s-s. 9(3), which was the first adjustment contemplated under the Agreement.  
>
assessment of positions:  
Page: 217  
[585] Assessment of the respective merits of the foregoing positions of counsel  
will be approached on the same principles of statutory construction as  
preceding paras. 561 to 565 applied to resolution of the extinguishment arm  
of the statutory interpretation issue. Focus will accordingly be directed to  
the plain meaning, contextual and purposive factors with an eye to the  
“framework of circumstances” which this case presents and to which Lord  
Denning stated statutory interpretations must be alert.  
*
plain meaning factor:  
[586] With due respect, it is difficult to see how the language of s-s. 9(3) can be  
construed to support NAPE’s position that it effectuated a suspension of  
scheduled dates for receipt of the pay equity wage adjustments, resulting in  
the payment falling due on April 1st, 1991, being treated as the fourth  
adjustment under the Agreement, with concomitant payout of the three  
deferred adjustments on April 1st, 1992, which happened to be also the fifth  
payment date for achieving full pay equity under the Agreement.  
[587] The lack of the language’s support for the foregoing construction posited by  
NAPE can be seen in the interrelationship within s-s. 9(3) between the  
phrases “the 1st pay equity wage adjustment date” and “the pay equity wage  
adjustment” as they are utilized in that subsection. As preceding para. 23  
already has observed, the chairperson viewed the former phrase as temporal,  
and the latter as quantitative dealing with amount. This is a reasonable  
construction of them.  
[588] Hence when s-s. 9(3) states that pay equity agreements may be implemented  
notwithstanding the restraints imposed in other provisions of the restraint  
legislation, it is asserting the time of “the 1st pay equity wage adjustment  
date” shall be “the date on which” the amount of “the pay equity wage  
adjustment is agreed upon” for any such pay equity agreement. The  
stipulation of “1st” in the former phrase is significant. In signifying this is  
the time of the first payment, it is reasonable to construe, as did the judge,  
that a shift of the implementation procedure was effected by the language of  
s-s. 9(3), and that the chairperson’s interpretation which was to that effect  
was not patently unreasonable.  
*
contextual factor:  
[589] The foregoing construction from s-s. 9(3)’s language is supportable by the  
context in which that restraint measure was enacted. Thus, the same  
Page: 218  
“extended budgetary explanation” given by the Minister of Finance that the  
judge singled out in the extract from his decision reproduced in preceding  
para. 79 as having been overlooked by the Arbitration Board’s chairperson  
in the latter’s majority finding that s. 9's Charter violation was not saved  
under s. 1, provides contextual support to the interpretation construable  
from the plain wording of that subsection.  
[590] From that budgetary explanation, it can be seen that the financial situation  
confronting the Province at the time of s. 9's enactment on April 18, 1991,  
was grave and serious, foreboding future difficulties in the provision of  
essential educational, health and other basic social services if measures were  
not taken to reduce foreseeable mushrooming deficits. In these  
circumstances, drastic budgetary cuts were imperative. One of these was  
elimination of the obligation to make provision for payment of wage  
adjustments under the Pay Equity Agreement with effect from April 1, 1988,  
as soon as the financial consultants had determined the quantum of those  
adjustments.  
[591] Furthermore, the circumstantial framework also shows that when the  
restraint measure enacted on April 18, 1991, was introduced for legislative  
consideration, it would have been known either that the consultants’  
calculations had been finalized; or at least, if there were no direct  
knowledge of the report’s completion, that the awaited submission of it to  
the steering committee was imminent. In either case, it is logical to regard  
the restraint measure of having been enacted in the expectation that the  
retroactive liability which had been accruing under the Pay Equity  
Agreement for wage adjustments would become payable in the current  
1991-92 fiscal year, ie. in the first year of the restraints, unless action were  
taken to extinguish the obligations that had accrued whilst awaiting the  
consultants’ determinations.  
[592] Faced with the expectation that this retroactive liability would fall due in the  
1991-92 fiscal year, the restraints were also being legislatively imposed in  
the context of the looming escalating deficitary situation which posed grave  
threat to the prospects of governmental capacity to provide essential  
services, and to the general economic security and well being of the  
Province, unless immediate counteracting actions were taken. This  
constrained Government to address commitments it made arising from  
benefits which were payable to all public sector employees. The  
circumstantial backdrop of the restraint legislation’s passage also indicates  
Page: 219  
that amongst those commitments was the retroactive liability for pay equity  
which would fall payable in the 1991-1992 fiscal year.  
[593] In the context of all these circumstances, it is reasonable to expect a  
governmental decision to shift the effective date of the wage adjustments  
under the Pay Equity Agreement from April 1, 1988, to April 1, 1991. In so  
doing, it must have been recognized by the legislators that the systemic  
gender discrimination visited upon employees standing to benefit under the  
Pay Equity Agreement would effectively be continued for another three  
years. In the result, the context lends support to the construction, which is  
borne out by s-s. 9(3)’s language, that April 1, 1991, should be regarded as  
“the lst pay equity wage adjustment date” referenced in that provision,  
thereby shifting the incremental implementation procedure, and  
consequently extinguishing the obligation to provide the retroactive  
adjustments. Therefore, from the context’s standpoint, the judge’s viewing  
of the chairperson’s majority interpretation that s-s. 9(3) extinguished pay  
equity obligations, and not just the scheduled payment dates, as not being  
patently unreasonable, and as therefore sustainable, is not assailable through  
NAPE’s alternate argument. To the contrary, the contextual setting of s-s.  
9(3)’s enactment supports that interpretation. In the result the provision  
must be taken to be treated as the “1st pay equity wage adjustment date”  
shifting, as the judge reasoned, the schedule for commencement of the  
incremental payments.  
*
purposive factor:  
[594] It now remains to address whether the purpose of the legislation also lends  
support to that interpretation. In this regard, it is important to keep in mind  
that the legislation’s objective of containing and reducing the forecasted  
ominous budgetary deficits was itself aimed at dispensing economic storm  
clouds harbingering serious hardships. The restraints on implementations of  
pay equity wage adjustments, and the freezes on salary scales, would have  
been enacted in expectation that they would constitute significant steps  
towards parrying the spectre of those hardships.  
[595] At the same time, those legislative restraints would have been regarded as  
necessary measures of assurance of continuing capacity to provide essential  
services, whilst at the same time allowing scope to embed pay equity and  
other wage scale increases into the structural financial framework of the  
Province. That that expectation was ultimately realized insofar as the wage  
Page: 220  
adjustments originally promised in the Pay Equity Agreement is concerned  
is noted at the outset of this judgment, in preceding para. 3, which mentions  
that satisfactory arrangements were made for payment of the adjustments,  
save those falling due in the fiscal years April 1, 1988 to March 31, 1981,  
with which this appeal is concerned. The legislative purpose having been to  
extinguish the obligations otherwise accruing within that three year span, it  
is reasonable to conclude that the Legislature would have contemplated any  
respringing of those obligations as risking re-gathering of those storm  
clouds.  
[596] Hence, as in the case of its context, the restraint legislation’s overall  
purpose supports construing s-s. 9(3)’s language as meaning that April 1,  
1991, should be treated as the “lst pay equity adjustment date” referenced in  
that subsection; and, not as the fourth wage adjustment date payable under  
the Pay Equity Agreement. Accordingly, the judge’s view that s-s. 9(3)  
effected a shift in the timetable for commencement of the incremental  
payments from April 1, 1988 to the same day in 1992, leading to his  
dismissal of the alternate position for quashing the Arbitration Board’s  
decision on the grounds of patent unreasonableness is supported by the  
provisions’ statutory purpose.  
[597] In the result, based on the foregoing analysis of plain meaning of s-s. 9(3),  
as well as the context and purpose of the enactment, NAPE’s alternate  
position, which accepts the scheduled obligations to make the first three pay  
equity adjustments were extinguished, but argues the Government was still  
obliged under the legislation to meet them on April 1, 1991, cannot be  
sustained. This position does not cast the chairpersons conclusion that s. 9  
had the effect “of extinguishing the obligations on government ... to provide  
pay equity adjustments for the period April 1, 1988, to March 31, 1991", in  
any patently unreasonable light. Thus, the judge’s upholding of that  
conclusion on judicial review, and his affirmation that the full entitlement  
that had accrued over that three year period was not payable on a reasonable  
construction of s. 9 is supported by the purpose of s. 9 and of the Act as a  
whole.  
÷
the further alternate position:  
[598] As preceding paras. 581-582 notes, counsel for NAPE is putting forth a  
further alternative position based on Article 4.01 of the representative  
collective agreement which, like the alternative challenge, also tracks the  
Page: 221  
union nominee’s dissenting reasoning. The part of the dissenting reasoning  
on this aspect of the union nominee’s decision is summarized in preceding  
para. 43. In a nutshell, it camps upon the employer’s undertaking in Article  
4.01 that there “shall be no discrimination” affecting wage rates by reason  
of gender. From this the union nominee concluded that once the financial  
consultants had finalized determination of “... the amount of the discrepancy  
attributable to gender ...” in their report of March 20, 1991, the continuance  
of “pay differential rates ... on the basis of sex” contravened that Article.  
[599] While likewise maintaining that the full amount required to achieve full pay  
equity was payable to all affected employees under Article 4.01 when the  
consultants’ report was completed on March 20, 1991, as had the union  
nominee before her, counsel conceded that there was a valid legislative  
restriction imposed by s. 5 of the restraint legislation on increases in pay  
scales which ended on March 31, 1993. She acknowledged that this freeze  
would have resulted in precluding reliance on Article 4.01 until April 1,  
1993. It is for this reason that this further alternate position earmarks April  
1, 1993, as the date when the full amount necessary to achieve pay equity  
was payable under that provision of the Collective Agreement.  
[600] With due respect this submission of counsel overlooks that s. 9, as well as s.  
5, of the legislation, would have had a superceding effect on pay equity  
entitlement provisions in the collective agreements. As has just been  
discussed, s. 9's effect was to extinguish entitlement to the full amount of  
the adjustments prior to the consultants’ report’s finalization. Canadian  
Legislatures are empowered to abrogate rights as long as they act within  
their constitutional powers, and do not violate Charter rights, or can  
establish justification if they perpetrate infringement of such rights. In  
extinguishing the affected rights in this case the legislature was acting  
within its justifiable powers. This is a full answer to the article 4.01  
argument.  
÷
disposition of issue:  
[601] The judge’s holding that no basis exists to conclude that the majority of the  
Arbitration Board made patently unreasonable reviewable constructions of  
s. 9 of the restraint legislation, should be affirmed. In the first place, the  
judge did not err in agreeing with the Board’s conclusion that s-s. 9(3) of  
the restraint legislation extinguished Government’s obligation in the Pay  
Equity Agreement to provide pay equity adjustments for the period from  
Page: 222  
April 1, 1988 to March 31, 1991. Neither did he err in concluding that  
Government was not required to pay the wage rate due in the fourth year of  
the Pay Equity Agreement, nor the three extinguished adjustments  
scheduled for payment in the fifth year under it, by virtue of either the  
restraint legislation or the collective agreement, as argued by counsel for  
NAPE.  
[602] In the result, this judgment has reached the stage of having completed its  
treatment of the substantive issues of jurisdiction, constitutional validity and  
statutory interpretation, listed as issues (i) to (v) in preceding para. 108.  
Attention will now turn to NAPE’s challenge to the use made of Hansard  
throughout these proceedings which is number (vi) on that list.  
The Hansard issue  
÷
scope of the challenge:  
[603] Hansard plays a prominent role in the foregoing treatment of the substantive  
issues of the constitutional validity and meaning of the legislative language  
in s. 9 of the restraint legislation. This is because considerable use was  
made of the legislative record of the Finance Minister’s “extended  
budgetary explanation” of the circumstances which had led to the cabinet  
decision to introduce the restraint bill into the Assembly. This resort  
pinpointed the objective of the impugned restraint measure and the  
contextual setting of its enactment which was essential to resolution of the  
justifiability of its Charter infringement and of its statutory meaning.  
[604] Heretofore this judgment has assumed on arguendo basis that the law  
permitted the recourse that was made to Hansard in these proceedings,  
whilst noting that the challenge registered against its use by the judge would  
be subsequently addressed. Before proceeding to deal with this Hansard  
issue, it should be acknowledged there is some room for doubt that that  
challenge was meant to extend question of the restraint legislation’s  
constitutional justifiability. This is because NAPE’s factum explicitly  
concedes that the chairperson’s reliance on Hansard in his “analysis under s.  
1 of the Charter ... demonstrates correct usage of extrinsic evidence”. It  
would follow from this that no exception was being taken with the judge’s  
avail to the legislative history of the restraint measure’s enactment in  
endorsing the chairperson’s majority decision. However, during her oral  
submissions, counsel for NAPE appeared to be questioning reliance on  
Page: 223  
legislative history as evidence of legislative purpose in the process of  
assessing whether legislation impugned under the Charter is redeemable  
under s. 1. This impression of extension of the Hansard challenge is  
reflected in preceding paras. 412-413, and elsewhere in this judgment.  
[605] It is freely acknowledged that this impression is at odds with authority  
quoted by counsel in her factum sanctioning the use of Hansard as evidence  
of purpose in Charter challenges, and that it is conceivable that the  
contrary stance perceived from her oral submissions may be  
misapprehension. Nevertheless, in order to assure that all challenges raised  
in this appeal have been fully canvassed, the ensuing discussion will  
proceed on assumption that the challenge extends to Hansard’s use in the  
analysis under s. 1 of the Charter, which premise will be addressed, albeit  
summarily.  
÷
historical perspective:  
[606] Historic reticence has traditionally existed over the use of the Hansard of  
debates in judicial interpretations of the import and meaning of statutory  
measures. An outline of the genesis of this reluctance is provided by  
Professor P-A Côtè in Chapter 4 of his text: The Interpretation of  
Legislation in Canada, 3rd Ed., (Toronto: Carswell, 2000). As that text  
notes, prior to the Charter’s advent, that reluctance even extended to the  
inadmissibility of parliamentary history in judicial interpretations in  
constitutional cases. The case highlighted in the text on this point is  
Attorney General of Canada v. Reader’s Digest Assoc. (Canada) Ltd.,  
[1961] S.C.R. 775. That authority involved an application for a declaration  
that provisions of Canadian excise tax legislation, and regulations  
promulgated under it, were ultra vires of the Parliament of Canada. In his  
judgment concurring with the Court’s majority Cartwright J. upheld the  
rejection of inadmissibility of a pronouncement made on behalf of  
Government by the Minister of Finance concerning legislative intent. Thus,  
reflecting the historical reticence to allow recourse to Hansard, Cartwright J.  
wrote in p. 792:  
C
In my opinion the learned Chief Justice of the Superior Court was  
right in rejecting the evidence which is the subject-matter of this  
appeal. It was conceded and is clear on the authorities that the  
statement of the Minister in introducing the bill would be  
inadmissible in aid of the interpretation of the statute as finally passed  
Page: 224  
into a law. I can discern no difference in principle to afford a  
sufficient reason for holding it to be admissible where, the words of  
the statute being plain, it is sought to show that Parliament was  
encroaching upon a field committed exclusively to the provincial  
legislature.  
[607] However, writing in the last decade of the 20th Century, Professor Côtè  
observed at p. 465 of his text that, “absent a constitutional context”, the  
principle of inadmissibility of parliamentary history had by then become  
“riddled with derogations and exceptions to such a point that we may ask  
whether it is on its last legs, if not completely finished”. Tacit confirmation  
of this viewpoint can be gleaned from the following acknowledgement by  
Cory J. in R. v. Heywood, [1994] 3 S.C.R. 761 at pp. 788-889:  
C
Despite the apparent merits of the rule that legislative history is  
inadmissible to determine legislative intent in statutory construction,  
this Court has on occasion made use of such materials for this very  
purpose.  
[608] This transit from foreclosure of any recourse to ministerial statements in  
interpreting the words of a statute to the practice of resorting to legislative  
history in construing statutory import and purpose may be viewed as part of  
the passage from stricter adherence to the literal approach in statutory  
interpretations to a purposive approach to legislative meaning. Under the  
former approach, inquiry is confined to the plain ordinary meaning of the  
legislative language employed, eschewing extrinsic evidence of purpose  
from sources such as Hansard. In the latter one, the context in which the  
statutory measure was enacted together with the purpose that prompted its  
introduction are considered along with the language giving expression to  
the statutory intent.  
[609] As has already been noted in preceding para. 563, the purposive approach  
which was endorsed in Lewis has been followed in the analysis of the  
statutory meaning of s. 9 of the restraint legislation in this case. The literal  
approach, displaced in transit by the more flexible approach referred to in  
Heywood, Lewis and other authorities, was articulated by Duff C.J. in The  
King v. Dubois, [1935] S.C.R. 378 at p. 381 thusly:  
C
... The judicial function in considering and applying statutes is one of  
interpretation and interpretation alone. The duty of the court in every  
case is loyally to endeavour to ascertain the intention of the  
legislature; and to ascertain that intention by reading and interpreting  
Page: 225  
the language which the legislature itself has selected for the purpose  
of expressing it.  
[610] It is not being suggested here that historical reference establishes any clear  
cut passage from the literal to purposive approach to statutory interpretation.  
However, it does show that in earlier times, as the foregoing passage from  
Dubois evinces, interpretation of meaning was generally confined to  
construction of the legislative language itself. Professor Côtè points out in  
pp. 477-478 of his text that signs of relaxation of the rule of strict  
construction of penal statutes actually began to appear at the beginning of  
the last century. Neither, as he also suggests there, should provisions in  
contemporary Interpretation Acts directing that statutes be given a liberal  
construction promoting their objects be taken to foreclose consideration of  
the plain and ordinary meaning of their language. In truth, neither approach  
is mutually exclusive of the other. The directions in Interpretation Acts to  
liberal and remedial construction promoting the legislative objective is tied  
to the statutory wording. Iacobucci J. succinctly made this point in the  
context of construing municipal enabling legislation under scrutiny in R. v.  
Greenbaum (M.), [1993] 1 S.C.R. 674 where he stated at p. 688:  
C
... a court should look to the purpose and wording of the provincial  
enabling legislation when deciding whether or not a municipality has  
been empowered to pass a certain by-law.  
[611] It is against this backdrop of the law, therefore, that attention will now  
center directly on NAPE’s contention that the judge erred in concluding the  
Arbitration Board’s majority made no error in referring to Hansard in its  
interpretation of s. 9 of the restraint legislation. The complaint will first be  
considered in the context of Hansard’s use with a view to determining the  
Charter violation was saved under s. 1. Then, the issue will be addressed  
in the context of its use in the interpretation of the meaning of the words of  
that restraint measure.  
÷
Hansard and the Charter:  
[612] If, in fact, NAPE’s challenge of the use of Hansard was extended to the  
constitutional context of the Charter, it is answered in the authority to  
which preceding para. 605 refers as having been quoted in NAPE’s factum.  
That case is Reference re Criminal Code (Man.), [1990] 1 S.C.R. 1123. It  
involved assessment of an attack on the constitutionality of prostitution laws  
enacted in the Criminal Code. Having found one of the targeted provisions  
Page: 226  
had infringed s. 2(b) of the Charter, inquiry turned to justifiability under s.  
1. In reasoning that the impugned measure’s objective of general  
curtailment of visible solicitations for the purpose of prostitution was  
unduly intrusive, Dickson C.J.C. endorses the legitimacy of resorting to  
legislative history in statutory interpretations in the context of justifiability  
under s. 1 of the Charter of the violated protected right and freedom. He  
signified this endorsation in the following passage from his judgment on pp.  
1137-8:  
C
It is legitimate to take into account the fact that earlier laws and  
considered alternatives were thought to be less effective than the  
legislation that is presently being challenged. When Parliament  
began its examination of the subject of street soliciting, it was  
presented with a spectrum of views and possible approaches by both  
the Fraser Committee and the Justice and Legal Affairs Committee.  
In making a choice to enact s. 195.1(1)(c) as it now reads, Parliament  
had to try to balance its decision to criminalize the nuisance aspects  
of street soliciting and its desire to take into account the policy  
arguments regarding the effects of criminalization of any aspect of  
prostitution. The legislative history of the present provision and, in  
general, of legislation directed to street solicitation is both long and  
complicated. The legislative scheme that was eventually  
implemented and has now been challenged need not be the “perfect”  
scheme that could be imagined by this Court or any other court.  
Rather, it is sufficient if it is appropriately and carefully tailored in  
the context of the infringed right. I find that this legislation meets the  
test of minimum impairment of the right in question.  
[613] It can be concluded from the foregoing passage, therefore, that the practice  
to which Heywood referred, of making use of legislative history to  
determine legislative intent in statutory constructions in the context of  
applications of s. 1 of the Charter, had been endorsed three years earlier in  
Criminal Code (Man.). It follows that this endorsation would include  
resort to extrinsic evidence such as the legislative history gleanable from  
Hansard. It is noted that such recourse to the record of legislative debates  
would be in keeping with judicial policy to allow wide evidentiary latitude  
in addressing justifications under s. 1 of the Charter of fundamentally  
entrenched rights’ violations.  
Page: 227  
[614] It, therefore, must be concluded that the use of Hansard in determination of  
the intent and purpose of statutory measures for Charter applications has  
authoritative sanction. Accordingly, if the complaint over the judge’s  
proceeding on the footing that the Board made no error in referring to  
Hansard extends to the use made of it in the Charter context, that challenge  
must respectfully be rejected.  
Page: 228  
÷
Hansard and s. 9's import:  
[615] As the foregoing brief sketch of it is intended to underscore, the  
contemporary approach to statutory interpretation has evolved from one to  
be ascertained within the four corners of the legislation, in Dubois’ words,  
by “reading and interpreting” the language, to one of factoring legislative  
context and purpose into judicial construction of statutory instruments as  
well as the wording. There is no doubt regarding the importance of the  
purposive component in present-day conception of the proper approach to  
statutory construction. This is verifiable in the passage quoted from  
Greenbaum (M.) in preceding para. 610. Neither is there any room to  
doubt the importance of purpose in the contemporary approach to legislative  
interpretations from other authorities such as Heywood, and Lewis whose  
direction to analysis on “wording, content and purpose” guided the  
approach to assessments of the challenges to the prior interpretations at bar.  
[616] This Court has already had occasion to discuss the function of purpose in  
contemporary constructions of statutory instrument in R. v. Boutcher  
(2001), 202 Nfld. & P.E.I.R. 243. That case, like Greenbaum (M.),  
involved interpretation of a penal statute. Boutcher’s majority judgment  
commented upon how the canon of strict construction of penal legislation  
came to be relaxed with the advent of the purposive approach, and how the  
two meld together so that legislative objective receives definition of its  
scope and is applied “in accordance with the strictures of the legislative  
wording” (see para. 62 of Boutcher). It should also be added that  
advertence to purpose serves as a screen through which one’s impressions  
of the plain meaning of the legislative text may be tested. All of this  
indicates, as earlier noted, that the strict literal and more liberal purpose  
approaches to statutory interpretations are not mutually exclusive, but  
interact one with the other to better assure that judicial statutory  
construction promotes legislative objectives.  
[617] While the legislation under scrutiny in this appeal may be viewed as having  
punitive aspects, it is not strictly speaking classifiable as a penal statute.  
This does now, however, detract from the importance of complying with  
Greenbaum’s instruction to look to “the purpose and wording” of s. 9 of  
the Public Sector Restraint Act, as was done in construing it. There would  
appear to be scarcely no more fertile field for ascertaining the purpose of a  
legislative measure than in the introductory and closing addresses as  
recorded in Hansard of the Minister responsible for piloting the bill  
Page: 229  
containing it through its various stages toward enactment. These addresses  
will almost invariably explain the governmental policy reasons prompting  
its introduction, and respond to questions that have arisen in the course of  
debate regarding the extent of its intended purpose. As observed in  
Boutcher, it appears somewhat incongruous, and not a little off-putting at  
times, to read in judicial decision that legislative measures could not have  
been meant to express the very purpose which those responsible for their  
formulation, and their textual content, state they mean. There would appear  
to be no richer source of legislative purpose than the Hansard of the  
introductory and closing statement of the Minister responsible for steering  
the statutory measures through the Legislative Assembly.  
[618] Hence on the basis of reason, fortified by such judicial authorities as  
Greenbaum, Lewis and Heywood, the challenge to the judge’s affirmation  
of the Arbitration Board’s use of Hansard in its interpretation of s. 9 of the  
restraint legislation, being issue (vi) in this appeal, must be rejected. In the  
result, the assumption that resort could be made to Hansard, made in the  
dispositions of the two statutory interpretation issues, was a valid premise.  
[619] This judgment will now move to the seventh and final issue that preceding  
para. 108 lists for consideration in this appeal.  
The bias issue  
[620] Although this issue is a preliminary one, it is being considered last. This  
was already noted in preceding para. 108, where it was indicated that the  
reasons for the order of its consideration would be explained. The primary  
reasons are that this issue was raised by Government in its cross-appeal;  
and, with it being apparent at this juncture that the judge’s affirmation of  
the disposition of the Arbitration Board’s majority is sustainable, the bias  
issue through which Government attacked that disposition has no immediate  
practical significance. However, inasmuch as the question of bias does go  
to the integrity of these proceedings, and in the event that this appeal does  
not mark an end to them, it appears apropos to state this judgment’s reaction  
to the bias issue.  
Page: 230  
>
prior determination:  
[621] It will be recalled that this issue arose as a result of the chairperson having  
advised at the outset of the Arbitration Board’s hearing that his spouse was  
a member of the Newfoundland and Labrador Nurses Union employed in  
the public sector. This resulted in a submission from Government that he  
should disqualify himself from the proceedings due to reasonable  
apprehension of bias. As earlier indicated, the members of the Arbitration  
Board unanimously dismissed that submission. The judge’s subsequent  
affirmation of that unanimity was appealed by Government in this Court.  
>
positions of counsel:  
[622] Government’s continued challenge rests on reasonable apprehension of bias.  
No allegation of actual bias was made at any stage of these proceedings.  
While conceding no grievance from the nurse’s bargaining unit in which the  
chairperson’s spouse had membership was amongst those before the Board,  
counsel for Government argues this is not a determinative factor of the  
reasonable apprehension of bias issue. In this submission, he relies on the  
fact, already noted in preceding para. 17, that one grievance was deemed  
representative of all grievances in dispute for the purpose of the arbitration  
at bar. From this standpoint, he argues the Board’s decision would be  
regarded by a reasonably informed bystander as setting a pay equity  
precedent for any bargaining unit within the public health care sector,  
thereby meeting the generally accepted test for reasonable apprehension of  
bias. On this reasoning counsel insists the membership of the chairperson’s  
spouse in the nurses’ bargaining unit was a sufficiently close connection to  
raise a reasonable apprehension of bias, despite the collective agreement of  
that unit not being amongst those in dispute through the grievance at bar.  
[623] Counsel for NAPE responds that the connection is too remote to ground  
such an apprehension. In doing so, she relies on the judge’s reasoning  
upholding the Board’s unanimous ruling. In his ruling, the judge pointed to  
an extract from a collective agreement executed on January 13, 1995,  
between Government and the Nurse’s Union to which the chairperson’s  
spouse belonged that was before him. The judge had underscored it had  
been agreed in that agreement that the first pay equity adjustment date was  
to be the date of its execution, namely July 13, 1995.  
[624] Thus, under the collective agreement from which the chairperson’s spouse  
stood to benefit, pay equity was not slated to come into effect until the  
Page: 231  
legislated restraints, on which the grievances at bar centered, expired on  
March 31, 1992. Moreover, there was no evidence that the date for the  
expiry of the Nurses Union’s restraint period would have extended beyond  
that date by reason of its commencement date for which, as preceding para.  
10 explains, the restraint legislation lent scope. In those circumstances, the  
judge held the hypothetical reasonable bystander “would recognize that the  
Board’s decision could not affect the NLNU membership, and therefore  
could not reasonably perceive bias”.  
>
affirmation of bias holding:  
[625] No exception can be taken with the reasonable bystander text for grounding  
a finding of apprehension of bias. The Supreme Court of Canada had  
occasion to enunciate it in Newfoundland Telephone v. Nfld. (Public  
Utilities Board), [1992] 1 S.C.R. 623, which addressed the consequences of  
a finding of reasonable apprehension of bias from strong statements made  
by a commissioner of the Province’s Public Utilities Board regarding the  
telephone utility’s policies respecting executive salaries in general, and that  
of the Telephone Company’s president in particular. At p. 636, Cory J., on  
behalf of a unanimous bench, had the following to say respecting the  
reasonable apprehension of bias test:  
C
Although the duty of fairness applies to all administrative bodies, the  
extent of that duty will depend on the nature and function of the  
particular tribunal .... The duty to act fairly includes the duty to  
provide procedural fairness to the parties. That simply cannot exist if  
an adjudicator is biased. It is, of course, impossible to determine the  
precise state of mind of an adjudicator who has made an  
administrative board decision. As a result, the courts have taken the  
position that an unbiased appearance is, in itself, an essential  
component of procedural fairness. To ensure fairness the conduct of  
members of administrative tribunals has been measured against a  
standard of reasonable apprehension of bias. The test is whether a  
reasonably informed bystander could reasonably perceive bias on the  
part of an adjudicator.  
[626] The nature and function of labour arbitration boards charged with  
interpreting rights under collective agreements, and with passing on the  
constitutional validity of legislation affecting basic fundamental Charter  
rights, are classifiable as adjudicative. Consequently, the same high degree  
Page: 232  
of fairness, free from even apprehensions of bias, as is exacted from public  
utility boards, is to be expected from those bodies. Hence, although the  
foregoing test was formulated with a different type of administrative  
tribunal in mind, the test against which the integrity of the decisions at bar  
must be screened is the test articulated by Cory J. in Newfoundland  
Telephone.  
[627] It is also accepted that the consequences of falling short of that test must be  
disqualification of the individual whose membership on the administrative  
tribunal gives rise to reasonable apprehension of bias, and in that body’s  
disposition being subjected to vitiation. However, there must, at the same  
time, be a sufficient nexus or connection between the stigmatizing  
circumstances and the dispute’s subject matter to warrant any conclusion  
that “a reasonably informed bystander could reasonably perceive bias ...”.  
[628] There is nothing that this judgment can usefully add to the judge’s  
reasoning for dismissing the challenge to the chairperson’s qualifications to  
have presided over the Arbitration Board. As did counsel for NAPE, this  
judgment adopts the judge’s reasoning and disposition of that issue. The  
underlying reason for its adoption is that the restraint legislation had no  
effect on the pay equity commitment to the Nurses’ Union. The collective  
agreement under which the chairperson’s spouse worked was not part of the  
arbitration and the legislation had no direct impact upon it. Hence, the  
connection was too remote to give scope for reasonable apprehension of  
bias by a reasonable informed bystander. Therefore, Government’s  
contention that the judge erred “in finding there was no reasonable  
apprehension of bias on the part of the chair from the employment of the  
chair’s spouse” is unsustainable.  
Disposition of issues:  
[629] Summaries of the substantive reasoning for disposing of the issues in this  
appeal have already been given at the end of the respective treatments of  
each category of them. There will be no need to duplicate those résumés. It  
is sufficient to state the results of the seven issues listed in preceding para.  
108, the upshot of which leads to dismissal of the appeal from the judge’s  
decision to grant Government’s application for judicial review of the  
Arbitration Board’s majority decision, which had allowed NAPE’s  
grievances alleging unjustifiable refusal to pay the retroactive wage  
Page: 233  
adjustments that Government had been obliged to provide under the Pay  
Equity Agreement.  
[630] The issues and results are as follows:  
C
C
(i)  
Did the decision under appeal err in holding the Board lacked  
jurisdiction to hear the grievances? YES  
(ii) Did the decision under appeal err in finding that s. 9 of the  
Public Sector Restraint Act infringes s. 15(1) of the Charter?  
NO  
C
C
(iii) Did the decision under appeal err in holding the violation of s.  
15(1) of the Charter was saved under s. 1 of the Charter?  
NO  
(iv) Did the decision under appeal err in agreeing with the Board’s  
conclusion that s-s. 9(3) of the restraint legislation extinguished  
Government’s obligation in the Pay Equity Agreement to  
provide pay equity adjustments for the period from April 1,  
1988 to March 31, 1991? NO  
C
C
C
(v) Did the decision under appeal err in agreeing with the Board’s  
conclusion that Government was not required to pay the wage  
rate due in the fourth year of the Pay Equity Agreement? NO  
(vi) Did the decision under appeal err in concluding the Board  
made no error in referring to Hansard in its interpretation of s.  
9 of the restraint legislation? NO  
(vii) Did the decision under appeal err in finding there was no  
reasonable apprehension of bias on the part of the Chair from  
the employment of the Chair’s spouse? NO  
Penultimate Commentary  
[631] The time elapsed between the appeal’s hearing and this judgment’s filing is  
attributable to its complexity, coupled with it having been preempted by  
other judgments that exacted attention. This case is illustrative of the  
difficulty in imposing artificial deadlines of general application for delivery  
of judgments. The backdrop of this case affords opportunity to comment on  
that subject.  
[632] Recently, there has been developed a general policy of guidelines which,  
reflecting the terms in which that policy is couched, has come to be  
described in terms of the “return time” for rendering judgments. The  
formulation of these guidelines has been the product of concern within and  
Page: 234  
without the judiciary over the time it sometimes takes for the delivery of  
judicial decisions. The fact that this concern is not of recent vintage, but  
has been harboured down through the years, does not detract from its  
legitimacy.  
[633] Without disputing the concern’s legitimacy, there are two points regarding  
the attempt at its remedy through the “return time” policy. The first relates  
to its efficacy. This case provides a concrete example of why it is  
impractical, if not impossible, to attempt to lay down general yardsticks  
governing reasonable time spans for the delivery of judgments. The  
complexity of the multi-faceted issues raised in this appeal rendered  
unrealistic expectation of response to the finite time limits contemplated in  
the “return time” policy. It is true that a measure of flexibility is  
incorporated into the policy for involved and complicated dispositions.  
However, the policy nonetheless contemplate finite time limits that are  
impractical to set in the abstract, without advertence to the particular case at  
hand.  
[634] It is doubtful, even under the widest latitude the policy might afford, that the  
time frame taken for delivery of this judgment would meet the policy’s  
temporal test. Yet, that time span was necessary if justice was to be done to  
the importance and substance of the substantial issues which this appeal  
engages. Given that the assumption of judicial office is conditioned on the  
singularly personal oath to do justice to all, and notwithstanding recognition  
of the legitimacy of the concerns over timely filings of judgments, and  
respect for those having responsibility for developing general policies, a  
judge can hardly be driven off from taking the time necessary to render  
justice by compliance with any artificial time limits. Hence, the inefficacy  
of “return time” rules of general application.  
[635] Apart from the policy’s inefficacy, there is an even more important reason  
for reservation over the policy’s attempt to meet the concern over timeliness  
in the rendering of judicial decision. It stems from the fact that the  
emphasis recently placed within the judiciary on “return time” for judgment  
has resulted in that catch-phrase becoming, if not a watchword, a cliché that  
has translated into external pressures to expedite judicial decisions. There is  
latent danger in this. It has potential to negatively impact upon the quality  
of decision and on judicial independence, both of which have relevance to  
discharge of the judicial commitment to do justice. In connection with the  
latter, as LaForest J. incisively put it in para. 329 of his dissenting opinion  
Page: 235  
in Re Provincial Court Judges, judicial independence “redounds to the  
benefit of the judged, not the judge”. The “judged” do not reap the benefit  
if external pressures result in judgments of quality below the standards  
which the public is entitled to expect; or, worse still, if they result in errors.  
[636] For these reasons, without discounting the legitimacy of the concerns that  
gave rise to it, there is reason for caution over the prospect that the  
pressures exerted through the external setting of artificial time frames for  
filings of judicial decisions will have a counter-productive effect. While  
there is indisputably validity to the time-honoured adage that justice delayed  
is justice denied, there is equal merit to the reality that justice is ultimately  
realized through the quality of judicial decision drafted in an atmosphere of  
judicial independence. While noone can disabuse the legitimacy of concern  
over the length of time in the delivery of justice, it is submitted that the most  
that can be expected from judges conscientiously bent on their  
responsibilities is that quality judgments be rendered in the earliest possible  
time frame necessary to formulate and deliver them. Time is only a  
threshold consideration. If it signals a chronic concern, then other  
considerations come into play.  
[637] It is for these reasons that it is respectfully submitted the imposition of  
artificial deadlines of general application for the delivery of judgments  
should be approached with studied caution. Deadlines and quantity cannot  
out trump judicial independence and quality, without deleterious effects on  
the measure of justice.  
Conclusion  
[638] While the judge’s holding that the Board lacked jurisdiction to hear the  
grievances challenging the constitutional validity of s. 9 of the Public  
Sector Restraint Act must be set aside, his conclusion that the Board erred  
in finding the infringement of s. 15(1) of the Charter was not saved by s. 1  
of the Charter is upheld. His conclusion that the restraint legislation  
extinguished obligation under the Pay Equity Agreement to provide pay  
equity adjustment for the period from April 1, 1988 to March 31, 1991, is  
also upheld, as well as his disposition of the other issues raised in this  
appeal. In the result, the appeal and cross-appeal are dismissed.  
[639] In reaching this conclusion, both the Government and NAPE have been  
successful in different issues raised in this appeal. This judgment must  
conclude, as it began, in expressing appreciation for the quality of both  
Page: 236  
counsels’ representations. The issues in this appeal were not only of high  
importance to the parties, but also were of significant public consequences.  
In all of these circumstances it is felt that this is a case for exception to the  
general rule that costs should follow the cause. In light of the special  
circumstances of this litigation, whatever the result, it would appear that the  
coffers of neither party should be depleted by the costs of the other.  
[640] Accordingly, the appeal and cross-appeal should be dismissed with each  
party bearing its own costs.  
W.W. Marshall, JA  
Steele, JA  
[641] I agree with the disposition of the issues as expressed by Justice Marshall in  
para. 630 of his decision and, accordingly, I would affirm the judgment  
under appeal. I also agree that the appeal and cross-appeal be dismissed  
with each party bearing its own costs.  
_____________________________  
G.L. Steele, JA  
Roberts, JA  
[642] I agree with Marshall, JA for the reasons given, that the chambers judge  
erred in holding that the arbitration board lacked jurisdiction to hear the  
grievance. I also agree with Marshall, JA that the trial judge was correct on  
all other issues. I would, accordingly, dismiss the appeal and cross-appeal  
and make no order as to costs.  
Page: 237  
____________________________  
D.M. Roberts, JA  


© 2022 IncJournal is not affiliated with or endorsed by the U.S. Securities and Exchange Commission